The Fallacy
of the 'Public Sector'
"capitalism stands its trial before judges who have the sentence of death in their pockets. They are going to pass it, whatever the defense they may hear; the only success a victorious defense can possibly produce is a change in the indictment."
by Murray N.
Rothbard
We have heard
a great deal in recent years of the "public sector," and solemn
discussions abound through the land on whether or not the public sector should
be increased vis-à-vis the "private sector." The
very terminology is redolent of pure science, and indeed it emerges from the
supposedly scientific, if rather grubby, world of "national-income
statistics." But the concept is hardly wertfrei; in fact, it
is fraught with grave, and questionable, implications.
In the first
place, we may ask, "public sector" of what? Of something
called the "national product." But note the hidden assumptions: that
the national product is something like a pie, consisting of several
"sectors," and that these sectors, public and private alike, are
added to make the product of the economy as a whole. In this way, the
assumption is smuggled into the analysis that the public and private sectors
are equally productive, equally important, and on an equal footing altogether,
and that "our" deciding on the proportions of public to private
sector is about as innocuous as any individual's decision on whether to eat
cake or ice cream. The State is considered to be an amiable service agency,
somewhat akin to the corner grocer, or rather to the neighborhood lodge, in
which "we" get together to decide how much "our government"
should do for (or to) us. Even those neoclassical economists who tend to favor
the free market and free society often regard the State as a generally
inefficient, but still amiable, organ of social service, mechanically
registering "our" values and decisions.
One would not
think it difficult for scholars and laymen alike to grasp the fact that
government is not like the Rotarians or the Elks; that it
differs profoundly from all other organs and institutions in society; namely,
that it lives and acquires its revenues by coercion and not by voluntary
payment. The late Joseph Schumpeter was never more astute than when he wrote,
"The theory which construes taxes on the analogy of club dues or of the
purchase of the services of, say, a doctor only proves how far removed this
part of the social sciences is from scientific habits of mind."[1]
Apart from
the public sector, what constitutes the productivity of the "private
sector" of the economy? The productivity of the private sector does not
stem from the fact that people are rushing around doing "something,"
anything, with their resources; it consists in the fact that they are using
these resources to satisfy the needs and desires of the consumers. Businessmen
and other producers direct their energies, on the free market, to producing
those products that will be most rewarded by the consumers, and the sale of
these products may therefore roughly "measure" the importance that the
consumers place upon them. If millions of people bend their energies to
producing horses-and-buggies, they will, in this day and age, not be able to
sell them, and hence the productivity of their output will be virtually zero.
On the other hand, if a few million dollars are spent in a given year on
Product X, then statisticians may well judge that these millions constitute the
productive output of the X-part of the "private sector" of the
economy.
One of the
most important features of our economic resources is their scarcity: land,
labor, and capital-goods factors are all scarce, and may all be put to various
possible uses. The free market uses them "productively" because the
producers are guided, on the market, to produce what the consumers most need:
automobiles, for example, rather than buggies. Therefore, while the statistics
of the total output of the private sector seem to be a mere
adding of numbers, or counting units of output, the measures of output actually
involve the important qualitative decision of considering as
"product" what the consumers are willing to buy. A million
automobiles, sold on the market, are productive because the consumers so
considered them; a million buggies, remaining unsold, would not have
been "product" because the consumers would have passed them by.
Suppose now
that into this idyll of free exchange enters the long arm of government. The
government, for some reasons of its own, decides to ban automobiles altogether
(perhaps because the many tailfins offend the aesthetic sensibilities of the
rulers) and to compel the auto companies to produce the equivalent in buggies
instead. Under such a strict regimen, the consumers would be, in a sense,
compelled to purchase buggies because no cars would be permitted. However, in
this case, the statistician would surely be purblind if he blithely and simply
recorded the buggies as being just as "productive" as the previous
automobiles. To call them equally productive would be a mockery; in fact, given
plausible conditions, the "national product" totals might not even show
a statistical decline, when they had actually fallen drastically.
And yet the
highly touted "public sector" is in even worse straits than the
buggies of our hypothetical example. For most of the resources consumed by the
maw of government have not even been seen, much less used, by the consumers,
who were at least allowed to ride in their buggies. In the private sector, a
firm's productivity is gauged by how much the consumers voluntarily spend on
its product. But in the public sector, the government's
"productivity" is measured – mirabile dictu – by how much it spends! Early
in their construction of national-product statistics, the statisticians were
confronted with the fact that the government, unique among individuals and
firms, could not have its activities gauged by the voluntary payments of the
public – because there were little or none of such payments. Assuming, without
any proof, that government must be as productive as anything
else, they then settled upon its expenditures as a gauge of its productivity.
In this way, not only are government expenditures just as useful as private,
but all the government need to do in order to increase its
"productivity" is to add a large chunk to its bureaucracy. Hire more
bureaucrats, and see the productivity of the public sector rise! Here, indeed,
is an easy and happy form of social magic for our bemused citizens.
The truth is
exactly the reverse of the common assumptions. Far from adding cozily to the
private sector, the public sector can only feed off the private sector; it
necessarily lives parasitically upon the private economy. But this means that
the productive resources of society – far from satisfying the wants of
consumers – are now directed, by compulsion, away from these
wants and needs. The consumers are deliberately thwarted, and the resources of
the economy diverted from them to those activities desired by the parasitic
bureaucracy and politicians. In many cases, the private consumers obtain
nothing at all, except perhaps propaganda beamed to them at their own expense.
In other cases, the consumers receive something far down on their list of
priorities – like the buggies of our example. In either case, it becomes
evident that the "public sector" is actually antiproductive:
that it subtracts from, rather than adds to, the private sector of
the economy. For the public sector lives by continuous attack on the very
criterion that is used to gauge productivity: the voluntary purchases of
consumers.
In another of
his astute comments, Joseph Schumpeter wrote, concerning anticapitalist
intellectuals, "capitalism stands its trial before judges who have the
sentence of death in their pockets. They are going to pass it, whatever the
defense they may hear; the only success a victorious defense can possibly
produce is a change in the indictment."[2] The
indictment has certainly been changing. In the 1930s, we heard that government
must expand because capitalism had brought about mass poverty. Now, under the
aegis of John Kenneth Galbraith, we hear that capitalism has sinned because the
masses are too affluent. Where once poverty was suffered by "one-third of
a nation," we must now bewail the "starvation" of the public
sector.
By what
standards does Dr. Galbraith conclude that the private sector is too bloated
and the public sector too anemic, and therefore that government must exercise
further coercion to rectify its own malnutrition? Certainly, his standard is
not historical. In 1902, for example, net national product of the United States
was $22.1 billion; government expenditure (federal, state, and local) totaled
$1.66 billion, or 7.1 percent of the total product. In 1957, on the other hand,
net national product was $402.6 billion, and government expenditures totaled
$125.5 billion, or 31.2 percent of the total product. Government's fiscal
depredation on the private product has therefore multiplied from four to
five-fold over the present century. This is hardly "starvation" of
the public sector. And yet, Galbraith contends that the public sector is being
increasingly starved, relative to its status in the nonaffluent 19th century!
What
standards, then, does Galbraith offer us to discover when the public sector
will finally be at its optimum? The answer is nothing but personal whim:
There will be
question as to what is the test of balance – at what point may we conclude that
balance has been achieved in the satisfaction of private and public needs. The
answer is that no test can be applied, for none exists.... The present
imbalance is clear.... This being so, the direction in which we move to correct
matters is utterly plain.[3]
To Galbraith,
the imbalance of today is "clear." Clear why? Because he looks around
him and sees deplorable conditions wherever government operates. Schools are
overcrowded, urban traffic is congested and the streets littered, rivers are
polluted; he might have added that crime is increasingly rampant and the courts
of justice clogged. All of these are areas of government operation and
ownership. The one supposed solution for these glaring defects is to siphon
more money into the government till.
But how is it
that only government agencies clamor for more money and
denounce the citizens for reluctance to supply more? Why do we never have the
private-enterprise equivalents of traffic jams (which occur on government
streets), mismanaged schools, water shortages, and so on? The reason is that
private firms acquire the money that they deserve from two sources: voluntary
payment for the services by consumers, and voluntary investment by investors in
expectation of consumer demand. If there is an increased demand for a privately
owned good, consumers pay more for the product, and investors invest more in
its supply, thus "clearing the market" to everyone's satisfaction. If
there is an increased demand for a publicly owned good (water, streets, subway,
and so on), all we hear is annoyance at the consumer for wasting precious
resources, coupled with annoyance at the taxpayer for balking at a higher tax
load. Private enterprise makes it its business to court the consumer and to
satisfy his most urgent demands; government agencies denounce the consumer as a
troublesome user of their resources. Only a government, for example, would look
fondly upon the prohibition of private cars as a "solution" for the
problem of congested streets. Government's numerous "free" services,
moreover, create permanent excess demand over supply and therefore permanent
"shortages" of the product. Government, in short, acquiring its
revenue by coerced confiscation rather than by voluntary investment and
consumption, is not and cannot be run like a business. Its
inherent gross inefficiencies, the impossibility for it to clear the market,
will insure its being a mare's nest of trouble on the economic scene.[4]
In former
times, the inherent mismanagement of government was generally considered a good
argument for keeping as many things as possible out of government hands. After
all, when one has invested in a losing proposition, one tries to refrain from
pouring good money after bad. And yet, Dr. Galbraith would have us redouble our
determination to pour the taxpayer's hard-earned money down the rathole of the
"public sector," and uses the very defects of government operation as
his major argument!
Professor
Galbraith has two supporting arrows in his bow. First, he states that, as
people's living standards rise, the added goods are not worth as much to them
as the earlier ones. This is standard knowledge; but Galbraith somehow deduces
from this decline that people's private wants are now worth nothing to them.
But if that is the case, then why should government "services,"
which have expanded at a much faster rate, still be worth so much as to require
a further shift of resources to the public sector? His final argument is that
private wants are all artificially induced by business advertising, which
automatically "creates" the wants that it supposedly serves. In
short, people, according to Galbraith, would, if let alone, be content with
nonaffluent, presumably subsistence-level living; advertising is
the villain that spoils this primitive idyll.
Aside from
the philosophical problem of how A can "create" B's wants and desires
without B's having to place his own stamp of approval upon them, we are faced
here with a curious view of the economy. Is everything above
subsistence "artificial"? By what standard? Moreover, why in the
world should a business go through the extra bother and expense of inducing a
change in consumer wants, when it can profit by serving the consumer's
existing, uncreated wants? The very "marketing revolution" that
business is now undergoing, its increased and almost frantic concentration on
"market research," demonstrates the reverse of Galbraith's view. For
if, by advertising, business production automatically creates its own consumer
demand, there would be no need whatever for market research – and no worry
about bankruptcy either. In fact, far from the consumer in an affluent society
being more of a "slave" to the business firm, the truth is precisely
the opposite: for as living standards rise above subsistence, the consumer gets
more particular and choosy about what he buys. The businessman must pay even
greater court to the consumer than he did before: hence the furious attempts of
market research to find out what the consumers want to buy.
There is an
area of our society, however, where Galbraith's strictures on advertising may
almost be said to apply – but it is in an area that he curiously never
mentions. This is the enormous amount of advertising and propaganda by
government. This is advertising that beams to the citizen the virtues of a
product that, unlike business advertising, he never has a chance to test. If
Cereal Company X prints a picture of a pretty girl declaiming that "Cereal
X is yummy," the consumer, even if doltish enough to take this seriously,
has a chance to test that proposition personally. Soon his own taste
determines whether he will buy or not. But if a government agency advertises
its own virtues over the mass media, the citizen has no direct test to permit
him to accept or reject the claims. If any wants are artificial, they are those
generated by government propaganda. Furthermore, business advertising is, at
least, paid for by investors, and its success depends on the voluntary
acceptance of the product by the consumers. Government advertising is paid for
by means of taxes extracted from the citizens, and hence can go on, year after
year, without check. The hapless citizen is cajoled into applauding the merits
of the very people who, by coercion, are forcing him to pay for the propaganda.
This is truly adding insult to injury.
If Professor
Galbraith and his followers are poor guides for dealing with the public sector,
what standard does our analysis offer instead? The answer is the old
Jeffersonian one: "that government is best which governs least." Any
reduction of the public sector, any shift of activities from the public to the
private sphere, is a net moral and economic gain.
Most
economists have two basic arguments on behalf of the public sector, which we
may only consider very briefly here. One is the problem of "external
benefits." A and B often benefit, it is held, if they can force C into
doing something. Much can be said in criticism of this doctrine; but suffice it
to say here that any argument proclaiming the right and goodness of, say, three
neighbors, who yearn to form a string quartet, forcing a fourth neighbor at
bayonet point to learn and play the viola, is hardly deserving of sober
comment. The second argument is more substantial; stripped of technical jargon,
it states that some essential services simply cannot be
supplied by the private sphere, and that therefore government supply of these
services is necessary. And yet, every single one of the services supplied by
government has been, in the past, successfully furnished by private enterprise.
The bland assertion that private citizens cannot possibly supply these goods is
never bolstered, in the works of these economists, by any proof whatever. How
is it, for example, that economists, so often given to pragmatic or utilitarian
solutions, do not call for social "experiments" in this direction?
Why must political experiments always be in the direction of more government?
Why not give the free market a county or even a state or two, and see what it
can accomplish?
Notes
[1] In
the preceding sentences, Schumpeter wrote,
The friction
of antagonism between the private and the public sphere was intensified from
the first by the fact that ... the state has been living on a revenue which was
being produced in the private sphere for private purposes and had to be
deflected from these purposes by political force. (Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy [New
York: Harper and Bros., 1942], p. 198)
[2] Ibid,
p. 144.
[3] John
Kenneth Galbraith, The Affluent Society (Boston:
Houghton Mifflin, 1958), pp. 320–21.
[4] For
more on the inherent problems of government operations, see Murray N. Rothbard,
"Government in Business," in Essays on Liberty (Irvington-on-Hudson,
N.Y: Foundation for Economic Education, 1958), vol. 4, pp. 183–87.
No comments:
Post a Comment