by Daniel James Sanchez
Friday is on the same beach, looking through a chest
full of odds and ends that has washed up from a shipwreck. He finds a thick
book with a cross on it. It is a King James Bible.
Later the two meet, see each other's finds, and agree
to exchange them.
If the spirit of Aristotle were looking down from
above, he might have (incorrectly) concluded from the exchange that the two
goods were of equal value, reasoning that
there would be no "exchange if there were not equality." [1]
On the other hand, the French statesman and economist A.R.J Turgot might have (correctly) concluded from the exchange that both parties
must have considered the two goods to have been of unequal value: that Crusoe considered the Bible to
be of higher value than the idol, and vice versa for
Friday. This prerequisite for exchange is called a "reverse inequality of
values."
As Turgot wrote,
Each would remain as he was … if, in his own mind, he did not consider what he receives worth more than what he gives. [2]
In other words, they would not have exchanged unless
their respective scales of values looked like this:
Crusoe
|
Friday
|
I. Bible
|
I. Idol
|
II. Idol
|
II. Bible
|
Because with every voluntary exchange each party gives
up a lower-valued good for a higher-valued good, every exchange is, by
definition, mutually beneficial: a win-win situation.
Pleased by their increases in utility, Crusoe and
Friday then look for other opportunities for exchange.
Both Crusoe and Friday have stores of timber and clay.
Crusoe has five equal stacks of timber, and two equal piles of clay. Friday has
the opposite: two equal stacks of timber, and five equal piles of clay.
Although they have different amounts of each good, they have the same potential uses for them. And they happen to value the various uses in the exact same order.
Here are Crusoe's and Friday's respective scales of
values, with what each does have in regular font, and what each does not have in italics.
Crusoe
|
Friday
|
I. 2 stacks of timber for building a hut
|
I. 2 stacks of timber for building a hut
|
II. 2 piles of clay for roofing a hut
|
II. 2 piles of clay for roofing a hut
|
III. 1 stack of timber for fuel
|
III. 1 stack of timber for fuel
|
IV. 1 pile of clay for making pottery
|
IV. 1 pile of clay for making pottery
|
V. 1 stack of timber for building a tool kit
|
V. 1 stack of timber for building a tool kit
|
VI. 1 pile of clay for lining baskets
|
VI. 1 pile of clay for lining baskets
|
VII. 1 stack of timber for building statues
|
VII. 1 stack of timber for building statues
|
VIII. 1 pile of clay for making masks
|
VIII. 1 pile of clay for making masks
|
Crusoe, with his five stacks of timber, has enough for
all of the above-listed uses for it (I, III, V, and VII). However, with his 2
piles of clay, he only has enough for his top-priority use for it (II).
Friday, with his 2 piles of timber, has only enough
for his top-priority use for it (I). However, with his 5 piles of clay, he has
enough for all of his above-listed uses for it (II, IV, VI, and VIII).
The two consider exchanging 1 stack of Crusoe's timber
for 1 pile of Friday's clay.
If Crusoe were to make the exchange, he would give up
the ability to build statues, but he would gain the ability to make pottery.
Making pottery (IV) is higher in his scale of values than building more statues
(VII), so he would be willing to make the exchange.
If Friday were to make the exchange, he would give up
the ability to make masks, but he would gain the ability to provide himself
with fuel for his fires. Fuel (III) is higher in his scale of values than
making masks (VIII), so he too would be willing to make the exchange.
Since both are willing, the exchange would occur, and
both would benefit by it. After the exchange, their scales of value are as
follows:
Crusoe
|
Friday
|
I. 2 stacks of timber for building a hut
|
I. 2 stacks of timber for building a hut
|
II. 2 piles of clay for roofing a hut
|
II. 2 piles of clay for roofing a hut
|
III. 1 stack of timber for fuel
|
III. 1 stack of timber for fuel
|
IV. 1 pile of clay for making pottery
|
IV. 1 pile of clay for making pottery
|
V. 1 stack of timber for building a tool kit
|
V. 1 stack of timber for building a tool kit
|
VI. 1 pile of clay for lining baskets
|
VI. 1 pile of clay for lining baskets
|
VII. 1 stack of timber for building statues
|
VII. 1 stack of timber for building statues
|
VIII. 1 pile of clay for making masks
|
VIII. 1 pile of clay for making masks
|
Notice how for both Crusoe and Friday, a higher-ranked
item is now regular font, and a lower-ranked item is now italicized. This
indicates a state of greater satisfaction for each.
They consider making the same exchange again. However,
now things are different. Since Crusoe has less timber than before, any given
amount of timber in his stock is more precious than before. And since he has
more clay than before, the prospect of acquiring any given amount of clay is
less appealing than before. And the reverse of the above is true for Friday.
(This is the state of affairs described by the law of marginal utility.) [3]
Now if Crusoe were to make the exchange, he would give
up his ability to make a tool kit in order to gain the ability to line baskets.
Lining baskets (VI) however is lower on his scale of values than the tool kit
(V), so he would not be willing to make the exchange.
If Friday were to make the exchange, he would be giving
up his ability to line baskets, but he would gain the ability to make a tool
kit. As you can see from his scale of values, this would be a beneficial
exchange for him.
Nonetheless, since Crusoe is unwilling, a completely
voluntary exchange is impossible in this situation.
After being refused by Crusoe, Friday considers
inducing an involuntary "exchange." After all, Friday is physically
stronger than Crusoe, due to a lifetime of hunting and hard labor in the wilds.
And let us say his conscience permits such a confiscation. Why give up any clay
at all? And why not take all of Crusoe's timber?
If the possibility for mutually beneficial exchanges
were due to one-time factors, and few future trades were expected, perhaps he
would. In fact, he might never have recognized Crusoe's "property,"
and might have resorted to force at the very beginning.
But Crusoe's relative abundance of timber and dearth
of clay, as well as Friday's relative abundance of clay and dearth of timber,
were due to ongoing factors. Crusoe
happens to be faster at gathering timber than Friday; plus, there are woods
full of excellent timber on Crusoe's side of the island. Conversely, Friday
happens to be faster at gathering clay than Crusoe; plus there is an excellent
clay pit on Friday's side of the island.
Because of these factors, it is likely that, if both
Crusoe and Friday continued to produce as before, there could be a perpetual
series of opportunities for mutually beneficial exchanges.
And, because of their respective advantages, there
would be even more opportunities for mutually beneficial exchange if Crusoe
were to focus entirely on timber, and if Friday focused entirely on clay. This division of labor would be far more productive
than their isolated labor has been.
This truly looks like the beginnings of a profitable
partnership. But it would all be jeopardized if Friday were to take the timber
Crusoe gathered against Crusoe's will. First of all, Crusoe might fight back,
and Friday may have to kill him to get the goods. Or perhaps after being
expropriated, Crusoe would sail off to another island. In either case, Friday
would be "killing the goose that lays the golden eggs." And even if
Crusoe were trapped and forced to gather timber for Friday, the productivity of
his reluctant, resentful labor would inevitably plummet (especially when the
costs and dangers of enforcement are considered).
Even without supposing any particular moral values on
the part of Friday, it is more advantageous for Friday to treat Crusoe as the
rightful owner of his timber, and to thereby preserve and intensify their
division of labor, than it would be to resort to force. If Friday is aware of
that fact, he will treat Crusoe accordingly.
This is true for all humans faced with a similar
situation. As Ludwig von Mises wrote,
Every step by which an individual substitutes concerted action for isolated action results in an immediate and recognizable improvement in his conditions. The advantages derived from peaceful cooperation and division of labor are universal. They immediately benefit every generation, and not only later descendants. For what the individual must sacrifice for the sake of society he is amply compensated by greater advantages. His sacrifice is only apparent and temporary; he foregoes a smaller gain in order to reap a greater one later. No reasonable being can fail to see this obvious fact.[4]
And this is of profound importance, because human life
is characterized by what Mises called the "universal law" of the greater productivity of the division of labor.
The greater productivity of the division of labor is
universal because of what Mises called "the manifoldness of nature," [5] which Mises divided into two parts:
First: the innate inequality of men with regard to their ability to perform various kinds of labor. [6]
Examples of this are Crusoe's and Friday's different
speeds at gathering timber and clay.
Second: the unequal distribution of the nature-given, nonhuman opportunities of production on the surface of the earth. [7]
Examples of this are Crusoe's proximity to a superior
source of timber and Friday's proximity to a superior source of clay.
Furthermore, even if Crusoe had been more productive
with both timber and clay, there would still be an incentive for him to divide
his labor with Friday. For example, if Crusoe were four times faster than
Friday at gathering timber, but only two times faster than Friday at gathering
clay, it would be more productive for Crusoe to let Friday specialize in
gathering clay, so he would be free to focus on his "comparative advantage": gathering timber.
Any productive inequality between two parties makes
for ongoing exchange opportunities and the greater productivity of the division
of labor, the preservation and intensification of which make for the importance
of social bonds.
If all men, and the resources that they had at their
disposal, were the same, there would be no need for the division of labor or
for social bonds.
Imagine if, instead of meeting Robinson Crusoe, Friday
met another Kalinago Indian just like himself named "Saturday."
Friday and Saturday have identical skills, and identical resources at their
disposal. Furthermore, the course of events never changes this. Friday and
Saturday each produce the same exact goods for the same exact purposes. They
would, at all times, have the exact wants, and the exact same means to provide
those wants. They would be of no ongoing use to each other.
If the earth's surface were such that the physical conditions of production were the same at every point and if one man were as equal to all other men as is a circle to another with the same diameter in Euclidian geometry, men would not have embarked upon the division of labor. [8]
In a world in which either (A) there were no greater
productivity in the division of labor, or (B) there were, but man did not
recognize it, there would be no impetus for the development of stable, lasting
social bonds. Men would live either in complete isolation, or, if the means of
subsistence were scarce enough (a likely prospect with economic autarky), in a
constant state of war. Under such conditions, there would have been no occasion
for the evolution of fellow feeling, the inculcation of moral values, or the
development of a legal code.
On the other hand, as Mises wrote,
If and as far as labor under the division of labor is more productive than isolated labor, and if and as far as man is able to realize this fact, human action itself tends toward cooperation and association; man becomes a social being.…The factor that brought about primitive society and daily works toward its progressive intensification is human action that is animated by the insight into the higher productivity of labor achieved under the division of labor.
This is why Mises called the division of labor
"the fundamental social phenomenon" and "one of the great basic
principles of cosmic becoming and evolutionary change." [9] He saw it
as so crucial in explaining the progress from beasthood to savagery, from
savagery to civilization, and from civilization to the world-embracing market
society, that he rechristened "the law of comparative advantage" as
"the law of association." The higher productivity of the division of
labor, along with the capacity of man's reason to perceive it, is the
primordial font from which sympathy, morality, law, and society itself all
spring.
Notes
[1] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, book 5, chapter 1.
[2] A.R.J. Turgot, Value and Money.
[3] Daniel James
Sanchez, "Mises on Marginalism."
[4] Mises, Human Action, chapter 8, section 2.
[6] Ibid.
[7] Ibid.
[8] Ibid.
[9] Ludwig von
Mises, Human Action, chapter 8, section 1.
No comments:
Post a Comment