The Road to Totalitarianism
by Henry Hazlitt
Totalitarianism in its final form is the doctrine that
the government, the state, must exercise total control over the individual. The American College Dictionary, closely following Webster's Collegiate, defines totalitarianism as "pertaining to a
centralized form of government in which those in control grant neither
recognition nor tolerance to parties of different opinion."
Now I should describe this failure to grant tolerance
to other parties not as the essence of totalitarianism, but rather as one of
its consequences or corollaries. The essence of totalitarianism is that the
group in power must exercise total control. Its original purpose (as in
communism) may be merely to exercise total control over "the
economy." But "the state" (the imposing name for the clique in
power) can exercise total control over the economy only if it exercises
complete control over imports and exports, over prices and interest rates and
wages, over production and consumption, over buying and selling, over the
earning and spending of income, over jobs, over occupations, over workers —
over what they do and what they get and where they go — and finally, over what
they say and even what they think.
If total control over the economy must in the end mean
total control over what people do, say, and think, then it is only spelling out
details or pointing out corollaries to say that totalitarianism suppresses
freedom of the press, freedom of religion, freedom of assembly, freedom of
immigration and emigration, freedom to form or to keep any political party in
opposition, and freedom to vote against the government. These suppressions are
merely the end-products of totalitarianism.
All that the totalitarians want is total control. This
does not necessarily mean that they want total suppression. They suppress
merely the ideas which they don't agree with, or of which they are suspicious,
or of which they have never heard before; and they suppress only the actions
that they don't like, or of which they cannot see the necessity. They leave the
individual perfectly free to agree with them, and perfectly free to act in any
way that serves their purposes — or to which they may happen at the moment to
be indifferent. Of course, they sometimes also compel actions, such as positive
denunciations of people who are against the government (or who the government
says are against the government), or groveling adulation of the leader of the
moment. That no individual in Russia today gets the constant groveling
adulation that Stalin demanded chiefly means that no successor has yet
succeeded in securing Stalin's unchallenged power.
Once we understand "total" totalitarianism,
we are in a better position to understand degrees of
totalitarianism. Or rather — since totalitarianism is by definition total — it
would probably be more accurate to say that we are in a better position to
understand the steps on the road to totalitarianism.
We can either move, from where we are, toward
totalitarianism on the one hand or toward freedom on the other. How do we
ascertain just where we now are? How do we tell in what direction we have been
moving? In this ideological sphere, what does our map look like? What is our
compass? What are the landmarks or constellations to guide us?
It is a little difficult, as nebulous and conflicting
usage shows, to agree on precisely what liberty means. But it isn't too
difficult to agree on precisely what slavery means. And it isn't too difficult
to recognize the totalitarian mind when we meet one. Its outstanding mark is a
contempt for liberty. That is, its outstanding mark is a contempt for the
liberty of others. As de Tocqueville remarked in the preface to
his "France Before the Revolution of 1789,"
Despots themselves do not deny the excellence of
freedom, but they wish to keep it all to themselves, and maintain that all
other men are utterly unworthy of it. Thus it is not on the opinion which may
be entertained of freedom that this difference subsists, but on the greater or
the less esteem that we have for mankind; and it may be said with strict
accuracy, that the taste a man may show for absolute government bears an exact
ratio to the contempt he may profess for his countrymen.
The denial of freedom rests, in other words, on the
assumption that the individual is incapable of managing his own affairs.
Three main tendencies or tenets mark the drift toward
totalitarianism. The first and most important, because the other two derive
from it, is the pressure for a constant increase in governmental powers, for a
constant widening of the governmental sphere of intervention. It is the
tendency toward more and more regulation of every sphere of economic life,
toward more and more restriction of the liberties of the individual. The
tendency toward more and more governmental spending is a part of this trend. It
means in effect that the individual is able to spend less and less of the
income he earns on the things he himself wants, while the government takes more
and more of his income from him to spend it in the ways that it thinks wise. One of the basic assumptions of
totalitarianism, in brief (and of such steps toward it as socialism, state
paternalism, and Keynesianism), is that the citizen cannot be trusted to spend
his own money. As government control becomes wider and wider, individual
discretion, the individual's control of his own affairs in all directions,
necessarily becomes narrower and narrower. In sum, liberty is constantly
diminished.
One of the great contributions of Ludwig von Mises has
been to show through rigorous reasoning, and a hundred examples, how government
intervention in the market economy always finally results in a worse situation
than would otherwise have existed, even as judged by the original objectives of
the advocates of the intervention.
I assume that other contributors to this symposium
will explore this phase of interventionism and statism rather fully; and
therefore I should like to devote particular attention here to thepolitical consequences and accompaniments of
government intervention in the economic sphere.
I have called these political accompaniments consequences, and to a large extent they are; but they
are also, in turn, causes. Once the power of the state has been increased by
some economic intervention, this increase in State power permits and encourages
further interventions, which further increase State power, and so on.
The most powerful brief statement of this interaction
with which I am acquainted occurs in a lecture delivered by the eminent Swedish
economist, the late Gustav Cassel. This was published in a pamphlet with the
descriptive but rather cumbersome title: From Protectionism Through
Planned Economy to Dictatorship.[1] I take the liberty of quoting an extensive
passage from it:
The leadership of the state in economic affairs which
advocates of Planned Economy want to establish is, as we have seen, necessarily
connected with a bewildering mass of governmental interferences of a steadily
cumulative nature. The arbitrariness, the mistakes and the inevitable
contradictions of such policy will, as daily experience shows, only strengthen
the demand for a more rational coordination of the different measures and,
therefore, for unified leadership. For this reason Planned Economy will always
tend to develop into Dictatorship….
The existence of some sort of parliament is no
guarantee against planned economy being developed into dictatorship. On the
contrary, experience has shown that representative bodies are unable to fulfill
all the multitudinous functions connected with economic leadership without
becoming more and more involved in the struggle between competing interests,
with the consequence of a moral decay ending in party — if not individual —
corruption. Examples of such a degrading development are indeed in many
countries accumulating at such a speed as must fill every honorable citizen
with the gravest apprehensions as to the future of the representative system.
But apart from that, this system cannot possibly be preserved, if parliaments
are constantly over-worked by having to consider an infinite mass of the most
intricate questions relating to private economy. The parliamentary system can
be saved only by wise and deliberate restriction of the functions of
parliaments….
Economic dictatorship is much more dangerous than
people believe. Once authoritative control has been established it will not
always be possible to limit it to the economic domain. If we allow economic
freedom and self-reliance to be destroyed, the powers standing for Liberty will
have lost so much in strength that they will not be able to offer any effective
resistance against a progressive extension of such destruction to
constitutional and public life generally. And if this resistance is gradually
given up — perhaps without people ever realizing what is actually going on —
such fundamental values as personal liberty, freedom of thought and speech and
independence of science are exposed to imminent danger. What stands to be lost
is nothing less than the whole of that civilization that we have inherited from
generations which once fought hard to lay its foundations and even gave their
life for it.
Cassel has here pointed out very clearly some of the
reasons why economic interventionism and government economic planning lead
toward dictatorship. Let us now, however, looking at another aspect of the
problem, see whether or not we can identify, in an unmistakable way, some of
the main landmarks or guideposts that can tell us whether we are moving away
from or nearer to totalitarianism.
I said a while back that three main tendencies mark
the drift toward totalitarianism, and that the first and most important,
because the other two derive from it, is the pressure for a constant increase
in governmental intervention, in governmental spending, and in governmental
power. Let us now consider the other two tendencies.
The second main tendency that marks the drift toward
totalitarianism is that toward greater and greater concentration of power in
the central government. This tendency is most easily recognizable here in the
United States, because we have ostensibly a Federal form of government and can
readily see the growth of power in Washington at the expense of the states.
It is not difficult to see why this is so. Obviously,
if government is to intervene in business, there cannot be forty-eight
different kinds of conflicting interventions. Obviously, if government is to
impose an over-all "economic plan," it cannot impose forty-eight
different and conflicting plans. Planning from the center is possible only with
centralization of governmental power. And so deep is the belief in the
benevolence and necessity of uniform regulation and central planning that the
Federal government assumes more and more of the powers previously exercised by
the states, or powers never exercised by any state; and the Supreme Court keeps
steadily stretching the interstate commerce clause of the Constitution to
authorize powers and Federal interventions never dreamed of by the Founding
Fathers. At the same time recent Supreme Court decisions treat the Tenth
Amendment to the Constitution practically as if it did not exist.[2]
A notable example of this tendency exists with regard
to labor legislation. Supreme Court decisions regarding the Wagner Act and its successor
the Taft-Hartley Act (legally, and essentially, a mere amendment of the Wagner
Act) have not only steadily widened the sphere of Federal regulation to cover
activities and labor relations that are primarily, if not almost wholly,intra-state, but have ruled that the states themselves
have no power over these primarily internal activities and relations if
Congress has chosen to "pre-empt" the field.
The third tendency that marks the drift toward
totalitarianism is the increasing centralization and concentration of power in
the hands of the President at the expense of the two co-ordinate branches of
the government, Congress and the courts. In the United States this tendency is
very marked today. To listen to our pro-totalitarians, the main duty of Congress
is to follow the President's "leadership" in all things; to be a set
of yes-men; to act as a mere rubber-stamp.
The dangers of one-man rule have been so emphasized
and dramatized in recent years — we have seen so many appalling examples, from
Hitler and Stalin to their many pocket-sized editions, the Mossadeghs and
PerĂ³ns — that any warning of this danger to Americans may seem needless. Yet
most Americans, like the citizens of the countries already victimized by their
native Mussolinis, may prove incapable of recognizing this evil until it has
grown beyond the point of control. One invariable accompaniment of the growth
of Caesarism is the growing contempt expressed for legislative bodies, and
impatience with their "dilatoriness" in enacting the "Leader's"
program, or their actual "obstructionist tactics" or "crippling
amendments." Yet in recent years derision of Congress has become in
America almost a national pastime. And a substantial part of the press never
tires of reviling Congress for "doing nothing" — that is, for not
piling more mountains of legislation on the existing mountains of legislation;
or for failing to enact in full "the President's program."[3]
If we ask how it comes about that Congress and other
legislative bodies throughout the contemporary world have tended to fall into
public disrepute, we again find that the answer lies in the apparently
unshakeable contemporary faith in the necessity and benevolence of a
continually expanding government intervention. Congress and the planners can
never agree among themselves on precisely what the government should do to
remedy some supposed evil. They cannot agree on an unambiguous general law,
whose application in specific cases could be safely left to the courts. All
that they can agree upon is that "something should be done." In other
words, all they can agree upon is that the government must intervene, that the
special area of economic activity under discussion must be
"controlled." So they frame a law setting forth a number of vague but
high-sounding goals and create an agency or commission whose function it is to
achieve these goals through its own omniscience and discretion. The National
Labor Relations Law (the Wagner-Taft-Hartley Act) is a typical example. It sets
up a National Labor Relations Board, which thereupon proceeds to become a
prosecutor, court, and legislative body all rolled into one, and starts laying
down a series of rulings and handing down a series of decisions, many of which
surprise no one more than the Congressional members who created the agency in
the first place.
From then on, Congress in that particular sphere is
treated mainly as a nuisance. The administrative bodies that it has set up
resent its "interference" and "meddling" with their
activities. These administrative bodies devote themselves in large part to
extolling "administrative discretion" at the expense of the Rule of
Law — that is, of any body of clear rules to be applied by the courts. Any
subsequent effort of Congress to reduce the range of administrative discretion,
arbitrariness, and caprice is denounced as "crippling" to
administrative bodies, and as interfering with that "flexibility" of
action so dear to the administrative heart.
Along with this growth of administrative agencies and
administrative power, less and less controlled either by Congress or the
courts, there has been a constantly widening interpretation of the President's
constitutional powers. This has occurred both in the foreign and in the
domestic field.
It is especially marked in the sphere of foreign
relations. The Constitution, contrary to the repeated assumptions of the
champions of Presidential omnipotence, nowhere specifically gives the President
power to conduct foreign relations. Specifically, he has merely the formal
power to "receive ambassadors and other public ministers." Perhaps
this implies power over the routine conduct of foreign affairs, which could
hardly be carried on by Congress; but it certainly does notapply to any crucial decision. For the Founding
Fathers gave Congress alone the power
to declare war. And they specifically provided that no treaty could be made by
the President without "the advice and consent of the Senate." In
practice, ever since George Washington, presidents have generally ignored the
instruction to seek the advice of the Senate in treaty-making. And in recent
years they have repeatedly tried to evade the requirement even for Senatorial
consent. They have done this by three extra-constitutional devices.
One of these is to frame and sign a complicated
multilateral treaty and then argue that the Senate must ratify it without
suggesting amendments because any attempt to introduce amendments would make
the whole treaty impossible.
A second device, coming more and more into practice,
has been to frame a treaty setting up an international agency which is
authorized from then on to take its own actions or makes its own rulings by
discretion. This applies to the United Nations, with its innumerable
sub-agencies, to the International Monetary Fund, and to the International Bank
for Reconstruction and Development. Once the Senate has approved such an
arrangement it loses any real say regarding the decisions of the agency it has
set up, though the President can still have some partial control through his
executive appointments to such a body.
The third extra-constitutional device is, of course,
that of resorting to an "executive agreement" instead of a
"treaty," claiming that this is just as binding on Congress and the
country as a treaty would have been, and thereby evading the Constitutional
requirement for Senate ratification. When the Senate tried to pass a clarifying
amendment (and missed only by a single vote the necessary two-thirds majority
for doing so) to assure the supremacy of the Constitution over treaties, and to
prevent back-door amendment of the Constitution through the treaty-making
device, President Eisenhower and his advisers opposed it. In this debate, the
pro-Presidential press, in its news columns, constantly referred to this
proposed amendment as an attempt to curb "the President's treaty-making
powers." They used this phrase repeatedly in face of the fact that there
are no exclusively Presidential treaty-making powers in the Constitution. The
President has no treaty-making powers whatever that do not require the advice
and consent of the Senate, and the concurrence of two-thirds of the Senators
present. The claim that there is a Presidential power of making "executive
agreements" with foreign nations binding on this country, which the Senate
has no right to control, is completely without foundation.
In the domestic sphere, the President's powers have
grown chiefly through the steady multiplication of Federal agencies. Many of
these, through their rule-making and rule-enforcing powers, and their wide
discretionary latitude, have become combined legislative and policing agencies
to a large extent outside the control of the Congress.
The major wars in which the United States has engaged
in the last forty years have also led to an enormous growth in the President's
so-called "war powers." Now there is no specific mention of "war
powers," or any listing of them, in the Constitution. This growth of war
powers derives mainly from the precedents created by the unchallenged
assumption or usurpation of such powers by presidents in the past. Hence their
steadily cumulative nature.
Finally, the mere habit of huge Presidential power has
led to the assertion of still more power. An outstanding example of this was
President Truman's action in seizing the nation's steel plants in 1952, in
order to force the steel companies to accept the wage decision of the Wage
Stabilization Board that he appointed. Attorneys for the Government blandly
argued, and Mr. Truman himself contended, that the President could do this
under his "reserve powers" or "inherent powers" in the
Constitution. This was again an assertion of powers that the Constitution
itself nowhere mentions. And though this claim was finally rejected by the
Supreme Court, it was only by a vote of six to three. Minority members argued
that the President could seize anything he wished under these so-called
inherent or reserve powers. Had this become the majority decision, no private
property anywhere in the country would be safe from seizure. Presidential power
would be unchecked and practically unlimited.
It should hardly be necessary to point out that this
constant expansion of the claims for Presidential powers has almost necessarily
been accompanied by a constant reduction of the powers and prerogatives of
Congress. Today we find increasing resentment even of the Congressional power
of investigation of the executive branch. This is surely a minimal power,
without which Congress could not intelligently exercise its other functions.
But Congressional investigations have in late years been constantly denounced
either on the ground that they prevent the executive agencies "from
getting any work done," or under the pretense that they undermine the
morale of Federal officials and are almost invariably unfair. It is ironic that
Congress, whose ability to check Presidential power has been steadily shrinking
in the last forty years, should today be more often than ever before accused in
the press of "usurping" the functions, powers, or prerogatives of the
President.
One of the remarkable developments of the last decade,
in fact, has been the frequency with which the President, on one excuse or
another, has "forbidden" members of the executive branch to testify
on certain executive activities before Congressional committees. More and more
of the activities of the Federal government tend to become "top
secret," even in peacetime. Congress is said to be prying into something
that is none of its business. People presuming to speak for the President have
frequently come close to asserting what we may call the principle of executive
irresponsibility or non-accountability — that is, the principle that the
President does not have to account to the elected representatives of the people
for his official actions.
One would think that the horrible examples of
Mussolini, Hitler, Stalin, Mossadegh, PerĂ³n, etc., would give pause to our own
advocates of more and more executive power in the United States. Why haven't
they done so? Partly, no doubt, from the deep-rooted habit of putting one's own
country in a category by itself, as if what went on abroad could have no
relation to anything going on at home. It is the old illusion that "It
can't happen here."
Another reason why these dictatorial trends abroad are
not related to our own domestic trends is that we are in the habit of using
different vocabularies to describe similar developments, depending on whether
they occur abroad or at home. We may call a foreign tendency a trend toward
dictatorship, but argue for the same tendency at home on the ground that we
need a "strong" executive.
Now there is, true enough, a possible danger of having
an executive so weak, so incapable of maintaining law, order, and firmness and
dependability of policy, that the executive weakness itself breeds a threat of
revolutionary uprising followed by dictatorship. But this happens only under
rare and special conditions, not a sign of which exists in present-day America.
At the moment of writing, the nearest prominent example we have of a
"weak" executive in the Western world is in France. But when we
examine even that case closely we find that the real defect in the French
system is less that the Premier lacks sufficient legal powers as long as he remains in office, as
that he lacks security of tenure. The French
Assembly can irresponsibly vote him out of power at any time. He has no
corresponding power of dissolution to force the French Parliament to exercise
its removal powers responsibly. Having no security of tenure, he is too often
paralyzed in action. Yet the French, instead of giving him the unequivocal
power of dissolution possessed, for example, by the Prime Minister of Great
Britain, have tried to solve the problem in the wrong way by often giving the
Premier in office "decree law powers" that he ought not to have. In
other words, the French, instead of forcing the Assembly to exercise its powers
of approval or disapproval responsibly, periodically give the Premier powers
that should be properly exercised only by a legislature.
Regardless of whether or not this analysis of the
present French situation is accepted as correct, it is certainly clear that
outside of France no major nation today suffers because of "too weak"
an executive. Most of the so-called "free" nations, including
ourselves, already suffer from dangerously excessive powers in the hands of the
executive, and above all from a governmentthat has
acquired dangerously excessive powers.
In a Federal government restricted to its proper
sphere, the President might properly be given more powers than he has at
present in some directions, and fewer powers in others. But anygeneral argument for a "stronger"
executive can seem plausible only as long as it remains ambiguous and vague in
its specifications. If we must speak in broad general terms, then we are
entitled to say in such general terms that the powers and the responsibilities
of the President have grown far beyond those that either can or should be
exercised by any one man.
We have now outlined what I have called the three main
tendencies that mark a drift toward totalitarianism. They are (1) the tendency
of the government to attempt more and more to intervene, and to control
economic life; (2) the tendency toward greater and greater concentration of
power in the central government at the expense of local governments; and (3)
the tendency toward more and more concentration of power in the hands of the
executive at the expense of the legislative and judiciary.
To these I am tempted to add a fourth tendency — the
pressure for a world state.
The addition of this will doubtless come as a shock to
many self-styled liberals and well-intentioned idealists who would regard the
establishment of a world state as the crowning achievement of liberalism and
internationalism. A little examination, however, will show us that the present
pressure for a world state represents a false internationalism and a retreat
from freedom. It is, on the contrary, merely the equivalent on a world scale of
the pressure for centralized government on a national scale. It aims to set up
the coercive machinery of a world state before the world is remotely prepared
in sentiments or in ideology to accept a world state. The zealots for such
machinery are too impatient to study the necessary preliminaries to a world
state (even assuming that a world state, which would concentrate all world
political powers in a few hands, is even ultimately desirable). Such zealots
for a centralized world government with coercive powers fail to recognize that
if international good-will and intellectual clear-sightedness existed on the
part of national statesmen, practically all the reasonable objectives of a
so-called world state could be achieved without setting up such a world state.
And until this good-will and clear-sightedness are achieved within individual
nations, the creation of a compulsive world state would be either futile or
catastrophic.
The pressure for a world state, in fact, represents
not true internationalism, but intergovernmentalism,
interstatism. It would lead to the setting up of machinery
for a universal and procrustean coercion. We seem to be moving, in the present
era, toward more and more restriction of the liberties of individuals by
governmental agencies. This is the tendency that has produced the pressure for
international price-fixing; for the creation of "buffer stocks" of
international commodities; the institution of international subsidies and
handouts; the paternalistic governmental establishment of industries in
"underdeveloped" nations without regard to their appropriateness,
efficiency, or need; and finally the growth of an international inflationism,
as represented by such institutions as the International Monetary Fund.
This whole tendency makes a travesty of international
freedom for the individual, which is the essence of true internationalism. For
true internationalism does not consist in compelling the
taxpayers or citizens of one nation or the inhabitants of one part of the globe
to subsidize, or give alms to, or even to do "business" with, the
citizens of any other nation or the inhabitants of any other part of the globe.
True internationalism, on the contrary, consists in permitting the individual citizen or firm in any
nation to buy from, or sell to, or trade with, the individual citizen or firm
of any other nation. It consists, in brief, in the freedom of trade advocated
so eloquently by Adam Smith in the eighteenth century and practically achieved
in the nineteenth — a freedom of trade that (notwithstanding scores of
international agencies and multilateral treaties) has now been destroyed.
We are losing our freedoms today, in brief, through a
false ideology — or, to use an older expression, because of intellectual
confusion. Nothing is more typical of this contemporary intellectual confusion
than the enunciation by the late President Roosevelt of the so-called Four
Freedoms. As George Santayana points out in a footnote in his Dominations and Powers:
Of the "Four Freedoms" demanded by President
Roosevelt in the name of mankind, two are negative, being freedoms from, not freedoms to. Had he chosen
the word "liberty," he would have stumbled on reaching these desired
exemptions, because the phrase "freedom from" is idiomatic, but the
phrase "liberty from" would have been impossible. "Liberty"
thus seems to imply vital liberty, the exercise of powers and virtues native to
oneself and to one's country. But freedom from want or from fear is only a
condition for the steady exercise of true liberty. On the other hand it is more
than a demand for liberty; for it demands insurance and protection by provident
institutions, which imply the dominance of a paternal government, with
artificial privileges secured by law. This would be freedom from the dangers of
a free life. It shows us liberty contracting its field and bargaining for
safety first.
The contemporary world has gone astray, in sum,
because it has sought freedom from the dangers and risks of liberty.
Notes
[1] Cobden-Sanderson, London, 1934.
[2] The Tenth Amendment reads: "The powers not
delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the
States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people."
[3] It is instructive to recall in this connection
that the 80th Congress, which President Truman condemned as a
"do-nothing" Congress, actually passed 457 private bills and 906 new
public laws — a total of 1363. This record was typical of our modern
legislative mills. The 79th Congress passed 892 private bills and 734 new
public laws. And so on.
No comments:
Post a Comment