Lecture to the memory of Alfred Nobel, December 11, 1974by Friedrich August von Hayek
The particular occasion of this lecture, combined with the chief practical
problem which economists have to face today, have made the choice of its
topic almost inevitable. On the one hand the still recent establishment of the
Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Science marks a significant step in the
process by which, in the opinion of the general public, economics has been
conceded some of the dignity and prestige of the physical sciences. On the
other hand, the economists are at this moment called upon to say how to
extricate the free world from the serious threat of accelerating inflation
which, it must be admitted, has been brought about by policies which the
majority of economists recommended and even urged governments to pursue. We
have indeed at the moment little cause for pride: as a profession we have made
a mess of things.
It seems to
me that this failure of the economists to guide policy more successfully is
closely connected with their propensity to imitate as closely as possible the
procedures of the brilliantly successful physical sciences - an attempt which
in our field may lead to outright error. It is an approach which has come to be
described as the "scientistic" attitude - an attitude which, as I
defined it some thirty years ago, "is decidedly unscientific in the true
sense of the word, since it involves a mechanical and uncritical application of
habits of thought to fields different from those in which they have been
formed."1 I want
today to begin by explaining how some of the gravest errors of recent economic
policy are a direct consequence of this scientistic error.
The theory
which has been guiding monetary and financial policy during the last thirty
years, and which I contend is largely the product of such a mistaken conception
of the proper scientific procedure, consists in the assertion that there exists
a simple positive correlation between total employment and the size of the
aggregate demand for goods and services; it leads to the belief that we can
permanently assure full employment by maintaining total money expenditure at an
appropriate level. Among the various theories advanced to account for extensive
unemployment, this is probably the only one in support of which strong
quantitative evidence can be adduced. I nevertheless regard it as fundamentally
false, and to act upon it, as we now experience, as very harmful
This brings
me to the crucial issue. Unlike the position that exists in the physical
sciences, in economics and other disciplines that deal with essentially complex
phenomena, the aspects of the events to be accounted for about which we can get
quantitative data are necessarily limited and may not include the important ones.
While in the physical sciences it is generally assumed, probably with good
reason, that any important factor which determines the observed events will
itself be directly observable and measurable, in the study of such complex
phenomena as the market, which depend on the actions of many individuals, all
the circumstances which will determine the outcome of a process, for reasons
which I shall explain later, will hardly ever be fully known or measurable. And
while in the physical sciences the investigator will be able to measure what,
on the basis of a prima facie theory, he thinks important, in
the social sciences often that is treated as important which happens to be
accessible to measurement. This is sometimes carried to the point where it is
demanded that our theories must be formulated in such terms that they refer
only to measurable magnitudes.
It can
hardly be denied that such a demand quite arbitrarily limits the facts which
are to be admitted as possible causes of the events which occur in the real
world. This view, which is often quite naively accepted as required by
scientific procedure, has some rather paradoxical consequences. We know: of
course, with regard to the market and similar social structures, a great many
facts which we cannot measure and on which indeed we have only some very
imprecise and general information. And because the effects of these facts in
any particular instance cannot be confirmed by quantitative evidence, they are
simply disregarded by those sworn to admit only what they regard as scientific
evidence: they thereupon happily proceed on the fiction that the factors which
they can measure are the only ones that are relevant.
The
correlation between aggregate demand and total employment, for instance, may
only be approximate, but as it is the only one on which we
have quantitative data, it is accepted as the only causal connection that
counts. On this standard there may thus well exist better
"scientific" evidence for a false theory, which will be accepted
because it is more "scientific", than for a valid explanation, which
is rejected because there is no sufficient quantitative evidence for it.
Let me
illustrate this by a brief sketch of what I regard as the chief actual cause of
extensive unemployment - an account which will also explain why such
unemployment cannot be lastingly cured by the inflationary policies recommended
by the now fashionable theory. This correct explanation appears to me to be the
existence of discrepancies between the distribution of demand among the
different goods and services and the allocation of labour and other resources
among the production of those outputs. We possess a fairly good
"qualitative" knowledge of the forces by which a correspondence
between demand and supply in the different sectors of the economic system is
brought about, of the conditions under which it will be achieved, and of the
factors likely to prevent such an adjustment. The separate steps in the account
of this process rely on facts of everyday experience, and few who take the
trouble to follow the argument will question the validity of the factual
assumptions, or the logical correctness of the conclusions drawn from them. We
have indeed good reason to believe that unemployment indicates that the
structure of relative prices and wages has been distorted (usually by
monopolistic or governmental price fixing), and that to restore equality
between the demand and the supply of labour in all sectors changes of relative
prices and some transfers of labour will be necessary.
But when we
are asked for quantitative evidence for the particular structure of prices and
wages that would be required in order to assure a smooth continuous sale of the
products and services offered, we must admit that we have no such information.
We know, in other words, the general conditions in which what we call, somewhat
misleadingly, an equilibrium will establish itself: but we never know what the
particular prices or wages are which would exist if the market were to bring
about such an equilibrium. We can merely say what the conditions are in which
we can expect the market to establish prices and wages at which demand will
equal supply. But we can never produce statistical information which would show
how much the prevailing prices and wages deviate from those
which would secure a continuous sale of the current supply of labour. Though
this account of the causes of unemployment is an empirical theory, in the sense
that it might be proved false, e.g. if, with a constant money supply, a general
increase of wages did not lead to unemployment, it is certainly not the kind of
theory which we could use to obtain specific numerical predictions concerning
the rates of wages, or the distribution of labour, to be expected.
Why should
we, however, in economics, have to plead ignorance of the sort of facts on
which, in the case of a physical theory, a scientist would certainly be
expected to give precise information? It is probably not surprising that those
impressed by the example of the physical sciences should find this position
very unsatisfactory and should insist on the standards of proof which they find
there. The reason for this state of affairs is the fact, to which I have
already briefly referred, that the social sciences, like much of biology but
unlike most fields of the physical sciences, have to deal with structures
of essential complexity, i.e. with structures whose
characteristic properties can be exhibited only by models made up of relatively
large numbers of variables. Competition, for instance, is a process which will
produce certain results only if it proceeds among a fairly large number of
acting persons.
In some
fields, particularly where problems of a similar kind arise in the physical
sciences, the difficulties can be overcome by using, instead of specific
information about the individual elements, data about the relative frequency,
or the probability, of the occurrence of the various distinctive properties of
the elements. But this is true only where we have to deal with what has been
called by Dr. Warren Weaver (formerly of the Rockefeller Foundation), with a
distinction which ought to be much more widely understood, "phenomena of
unorganized complexity," in contrast to those "phenomena of organized
complexity" with which we have to deal in the social sciences.2 Organized
complexity here means that the character of the structures showing it depends
not only on the properties of the individual elements of which they are
composed, and the relative frequency with which they occur, but also on the manner
in which the individual elements are connected with each other. In the
explanation of the working of such structures we can for this reason not
replace the information about the individual elements by statistical
information, but require full information about each element if from our theory
we are to derive specific predictions about individual events. Without such
specific information about the individual elements we shall be confined to what
on another occasion I have called mere pattern predictions - predictions of
some of the general attributes of the structures that will form themselves, but
not containing specific statements about the individual elements of which the
structures will be made up.3
This is
particularly true of our theories accounting for the determination of the
systems of relative prices and wages that will form themselves on a
wellfunctioning market. Into the determination of these prices and wages there
will enter the effects of particular information possessed by every one of the
participants in the market process - a sum of facts which in their totality
cannot be known to the scientific observer, or to any other single brain. It is
indeed the source of the superiority of the market order, and the reason why,
when it is not suppressed by the powers of government, it regularly displaces
other types of order, that in the resulting allocation of resources more of the
knowledge of particular facts will be utilized which exists only dispersed
among uncounted persons, than any one person can possess. But because we, the
observing scientists, can thus never know all the determinants of such an
order, and in consequence also cannot know at which particular structure of
prices and wages demand would everywhere equal supply, we also cannot measure
the deviations from that order; nor can we statistically test our theory that
it is the deviations from that "equilibrium" system of prices and
wages which make it impossible to sell some of the products and services at the
prices at which they are offered.
Before I
continue with my immediate concern, the effects of all this on the employment
policies currently pursued, allow me to define more specifically the inherent
limitations of our numerical knowledge which are so often overlooked. I want to
do this to avoid giving the impression that I generally reject the mathematical
method in economics. I regard it in fact as the great advantage of the
mathematical technique that it allows us to describe, by means of algebraic
equations, the general character of a pattern even where we are ignorant of the
numerical values which will determine its particular manifestation. We could
scarcely have achieved that comprehensive picture of the mutual interdependencies
of the different events in a market without this algebraic technique. It has
led to the illusion, however, that we can use this technique for the
determination and prediction of the numerical values of those magnitudes; and
this has led to a vain search for quantitative or numerical constants. This
happened in spite of the fact that the modern founders of mathematical
economics had no such illusions. It is true that their systems of equations
describing the pattern of a market equilibrium are so framed that if we were
able to fill in all the blanks of the abstract formulae, i.e. if we knew all
the parameters of these equations, we could calculate the prices and quantities
of all commodities and services sold. But, as Vilfredo Pareto, one of the
founders of this theory, clearly stated, its purpose cannot be "to arrive
at a numerical calculation of prices", because, as he said, it would be
"absurd" to assume that we could ascertain all the data.4 Indeed,
the chief point was already seen by those remarkable anticipators of modern
economics, the Spanish schoolmen of the sixteenth century, who emphasized that
what they called pretium mathematicum, the mathematical price,
depended on so many particular circumstances that it could never be known to
man but was known only to God.5 I
sometimes wish that our mathematical economists would take this to heart. I
must confess that I still doubt whether their search for measurable magnitudes
has made significant contributions to ourtheoretical understanding
of economic phenomena - as distinct from their value as a description of
particular situations. Nor am I prepared to accept the excuse that this branch
of research is still very young: Sir William Petty, the founder of
econometrics, was after all a somewhat senior colleague of Sir Isaac Newton in
the Royal Society!
There may be few instances in which the superstition that only measurable magnitudes can be important has done positive harm in the economic field: but the present inflation and employment problems are a very serious one. Its effect has been that what is probably the true cause of extensive unemployment has been disregarded by the scientistically minded majority of economists, because its operation could not be confirmed by directly observable relations between measurable magnitudes, and that an almost exclusive concentration on quantitatively measurable surface phenomena has produced a policy which has made matters worse.
It has, of
course, to be readily admitted that the kind of theory which I regard as the
true explanation of unemployment is a theory of somewhat limited content
because it allows us to make only very general predictions of the kind of
events which we must expect in a given situation. But the effects on policy of
the more ambitious constructions have not been very fortunate and I confess
that I prefer true but imperfect knowledge, even if it leaves much indetermined
and unpredictable, to a pretence of exact knowledge that is likely to be false.
The credit which the apparent conformity with recognized scientific standards
can gain for seemingly simple but false theories may, as the present instance
shows, have grave consequences.
In fact, in
the case discussed, the very measures which the dominant
"macro-economic" theory has recommended as a remedy for unemployment,
namely the increase of aggregate demand, have become a cause of a very
extensive misallocation of resources which is likely to make later large-scale
unemployment inevitable. The continuous injection of additional amounts of
money at points of the economic system where it creates a temporary demand
which must cease when the increase of the quantity of money stops or slows
down, together with the expectation of a continuing rise of prices, draws
labour and other resources into employments which can last only so long as the
increase of the quantity of money continues at the same rate - or perhaps even
only so long as it continues to accelerate at a given rate. What this policy
has produced is not so much a level of employment that could not have been
brought about in other ways, as a distribution of employment which cannot be
indefinitely maintained and which after some time can be maintained only by a
rate of inflation which would rapidly lead to a disorganisation of all economic
activity. The fact is that by a mistaken theoretical view we have been led into
a precarious position in which we cannot prevent substantial unemployment from
re-appearing; not because, as this view is sometimes misrepresented, this
unemployment is deliberately brought about as a means to combat inflation, but
because it is now bound to occur as a deeply regrettable but inescapable
consequence of the mistaken policies of the past as soon as inflation ceases to
accelerate.
I must,
however, now leave these problems of immediate practical importance which I
have introduced chiefly as an illustration of the momentous consequences that
may follow from errors concerning abstract problems of the philosophy of
science. There is as much reason to be apprehensive about the long run dangers
created in a much wider field by the uncritical acceptance of assertions which
have the appearance of being scientific as there is with
regard to the problems I have just discussed. What I mainly wanted to bring out
by the topical illustration is that certainly in my field, but I believe also
generally in the sciences of man, what looks superficially like the most
scientific procedure is often the most unscientific, and, beyond this, that in
these fields there are definite limits to what we can expect science to
achieve. This means that to entrust to science - or to deliberate control
according to scientific principles - more than scientific method can achieve
may have deplorable effects. The progress of the natural sciences in modern
times has of course so much exceeded all expectations that any suggestion that
there may be some limits to it is bound to arouse suspicion. Especially all
those will resist such an insight who have hoped that our increasing power of
prediction and control, generally regarded as the characteristic result of
scientific advance, applied to the processes of society, would soon enable us
to mould society entirely to our liking. It is indeed true that, in contrast to
the exhilaration which the discoveries of the physical sciences tend to
produce, the insights which we gain from the study of society more often have a
dampening effect on our aspirations; and it is perhaps not surprising that the
more impetuous younger members of our profession are not always prepared to
accept this. Yet the confidence in the unlimited power of science is only too
often based on a false belief that the scientific method consists in the
application of a ready-made technique, or in imitating the form rather than the
substance of scientific procedure, as if one needed only to follow some cooking
recipes to solve all social problems. It sometimes almost seems as if the
techniques of science were more easily learnt than the thinking that shows us
what the problems are and how to approach them.
The conflict
between what in its present mood the public expects science to achieve in
satisfaction of popular hopes and what is really in its power is a serious
matter because, even if the true scientists should all recognize the
limitations of what they can do in the field of human affairs, so long as the public
expects more there will always be some who will pretend, and perhaps honestly
believe, that they can do more to meet popular demands than is really in their
power. It is often difficult enough for the expert, and certainly in many
instances impossible for the layman, to distinguish between legitimate and
illegitimate claims advanced in the name of science. The enormous publicity
recently given by the media to a report pronouncing in the name of science
on The Limits to Growth, and the silence of the same media about
the devastating criticism this report has received from the competent experts6, must make
one feel somewhat apprehensive about the use to which the prestige of science
can be put. But it is by no means only in the field of economics that
far-reaching claims are made on behalf of a more scientific direction of all
human activities and the desirability of replacing spontaneous processes by
"conscious human control". If I am not mistaken, psychology,
psychiatry and some branches of sociology, not to speak about the so-called
philosophy of history, are even more affected by what I have called the
scientistic prejudice, and by specious claims of what science can achieve.7
If we are to
safeguard the reputation of science, and to prevent the arrogation of knowledge
based on a superficial similarity of procedure with that of the physical
sciences, much effort will have to be directed toward debunking such
arrogations, some of which have by now become the vested interests of
established university departments. We cannot be grateful enough to such modern
philosophers of science as Sir Karl Popper for giving us a test by which we can
distinguish between what we may accept as scientific and what not - a test
which I am sure some doctrines now widely accepted as scientific would not
pass. There are some special problems, however, in connection with those
essentially complex phenomena of which social structures are so important an
instance, which make me wish to restate in conclusion in more general terms the
reasons why in these fields not only are there only absolute obstacles to the
prediction of specific events, but why to act as if we possessed scientific
knowledge enabling us to transcend them may itself become a serious obstacle to
the advance of the human intellect.
The chief
point we must remember is that the great and rapid advance of the physical
sciences took place in fields where it proved that explanation and prediction
could be based on laws which accounted for the observed phenomena as functions
of comparatively few variables - either particular facts or relative
frequencies of events. This may even be the ultimate reason why we single out
these realms as "physical" in contrast to those more highly organized
structures which I have here called essentially complex phenomena. There is no
reason why the position must be the same in the latter as in the former fields.
The difficulties which we encounter in the latter are not, as one might at
first suspect, difficulties about formulating theories for the explanation of
the observed events - although they cause also special difficulties about
testing proposed explanations and therefore about eliminating bad theories.
They are due to the chief problem which arises when we apply our theories to
any particular situation in the real world. A theory of essentially complex
phenomena must refer to a large number of particular facts; and to derive a
prediction from it, or to test it, we have to ascertain all these particular
facts. Once we succeeded in this there should be no particular difficulty about
deriving testable predictions - with the help of modern computers it should be
easy enough to insert these data into the appropriate blanks of the theoretical
formulae and to derive a prediction. The real difficulty, to the solution of
which science has little to contribute, and which is sometimes indeed
insoluble, consists in the ascertainment of the particular facts.
A simple
example will show the nature of this difficulty. Consider some ball game played
by a few people of approximately equal skill. If we knew a few particular facts
in addition to our general knowledge of the ability of the individual players,
such as their state of attention, their perceptions and the state of their
hearts, lungs, muscles etc. at each moment of the game, we could probably predict
the outcome. Indeed, if we were familiar both with the game and the teams we
should probably have a fairly shrewd idea on what the outcome will depend. But
we shall of course not be able to ascertain those facts and in consequence the
result of the game will be outside the range of the scientifically predictable,
however well we may know what effects particular events would have on the
result of the game. This does not mean that we can make no predictions at all
about the course of such a game. If we know the rules of the different games we
shall, in watching one, very soon know which game is being played and what
kinds of actions we can expect and what kind not. But our capacity to predict
will be confined to such general characteristics of the events to be expected
and not include the capacity of predicting particular individual events.
This
corresponds to what I have called earlier the mere pattern predictions to which
we are increasingly confined as we penetrate from the realm in which relatively
simple laws prevail into the range of phenomena where organized complexity
rules. As we advance we find more and more frequently that we can in fact
ascertain only some but not all the particular circumstances which determine
the outcome of a given process; and in consequence we are able to predict only
some but not all the properties of the result we have to expect. Often all that
we shall be able to predict will be some abstract characteristic of the pattern
that will appear - relations between kinds of elements about which individually
we know very little. Yet, as I am anxious to repeat, we will still achieve
predictions which can be falsified and which therefore are of empirical
significance.
Of course,
compared with the precise predictions we have learnt to expect in the physical
sciences, this sort of mere pattern predictions is a second best with which one
does not like to have to be content. Yet the danger of which I want to warn is
precisely the belief that in order to have a claim to be accepted as scientific
it is necessary to achieve more. This way lies charlatanism and worse. To act
on the belief that we possess the knowledge and the power which enable us to
shape the processes of society entirely to our liking, knowledge which in fact
we do not possess, is likely to make us do much harm. In the
physical sciences there may be little objection to trying to do the impossible;
one might even feel that one ought not to discourage the over-confident because
their experiments may after all produce some new insights. But in the social
field the erroneous belief that the exercise of some power would have
beneficial consequences is likely to lead to a new power to coerce other men
being conferred on some authority. Even if such power is not in itself bad, its
exercise is likely to impede the functioning of those spontaneous ordering
forces by which, without understanding them, man is in fact so largely assisted
in the pursuit of his aims. We are only beginning to understand on how subtle a
communication system the functioning of an advanced industrial society is based
- a communications system which we call the market and which turns out to be a
more efficient mechanism for digesting dispersed information than any that man
has deliberately designed.
If man is
not to do more harm than good in his efforts to improve the social order, he
will have to learn that in this, as in all other fields where essential
complexity of an organized kind prevails, he cannot acquire the full knowledge
which would make mastery of the events possible. He will therefore have to use
what knowledge he can achieve, not to shape the results as the craftsman shapes
his handiwork, but rather to cultivate a growth by providing the appropriate
environment, in the manner in which the gardener does this for his plants.
There is danger in the exuberant feeling of ever growing power which the
advance of the physical sciences has engendered and which tempts man to try,
"dizzy with success", to use a characteristic phrase of early
communism, to subject not only our natural but also our human environment to
the control of a human will. The recognition of the insuperable limits to his
knowledge ought indeed to teach the student of society a lesson of humility
which should guard him against becoming an accomplice in men's fatal striving
to control society - a striving which makes him not only a tyrant over his
fellows, but which may well make him the destroyer of a civilization which no
brain has designed but which has grown from the free efforts of millions of
individuals.
1. "Scientism and the Study of Society", Economica,
vol. IX, no. 35, August 1942, reprinted in The Counter-Revolution of
Science, Glencoe, Ill., 1952, p. 15 of this reprint.
2. Warren Weaver, "A Quarter Century in the Natural
Sciences", The Rockefeller Foundation Annual Report 1958,
chapter I, "Science and Complexity".
3. See my essay "The Theory of Complex Phenomena" in The
Critical Approach to Science and Philosophy. Essays in Honor of K.R. Popper,
ed. M. Bunge, New York 1964, and reprinted (with additions) in my Studies
in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, London and Chicago 1967.
5. See, e.g., Luis Molina, De iustitia et iure, Cologne
1596-1600, tom. II, disp. 347, no. 3, and particularly Johannes de Lugo, Disputationum
de iustitia et iure tomus secundus, Lyon 1642, disp. 26, sect. 4, no. 40.
6. See The Limits to Growth: A Report of the Club of Rome's Project
on the Predicament of Mankind, New York 1972; for a systematic examination
of this by a competent economist cf. Wilfred Beckerman, In Defence of
Economic Growth, London 1974, and, for a list of earlier criticisms by
experts, Gottfried Haberler, Economic Growth and Stability, Los
Angeles 1974, who rightly calls their effect "devastating".
7. I have given some illustrations of these tendencies in other fields in
my inaugural lecture as Visiting Professor at the University of Salzburg, Die
Irrtümer des Konstruktivismus und die Grundlagen legitimer Kritik
gesellschaftlicher Gebilde, Munich 1970, now reissued for the Walter Eucken
Institute, at Freiburg i.Brg. by J.C.B. Mohr, Tübingen 1975.
No comments:
Post a Comment