By Robert
Higgs
Perhaps
you have been struck, as I have been repeatedly over the years, by the way in
which certain disputes are framed. A writer, reporter, or discussant recognizes
a difference of views on some matter: A maintains X, and B maintains Y. Yet,
even though a difference is acknowledged, the question is resolved by
concluding that X must be the case because B has not proven that Y is
the case. This conclusion is often reached only on the assumption
that A does not, or should not, bear a similar burden of proof.
Libertarians, for example,
constantly encounter this situation when they argue against state provision of
some good or service currently provided by the state. The libertarians might
argue, say, that private suppliers can provide personal security in
better quality or at lower cost than the government police can. Critics claim
that the
libertarians are wrong and note that the libertarians have not conclusively proven that private provision is better. Alternatively, critics sometimes claim that if private provision were actually better it would have already prevailed, conveniently ignoring the various ways in which the government has outlawed or burdened private provision, to destroy or cripple private competition with the state.
libertarians are wrong and note that the libertarians have not conclusively proven that private provision is better. Alternatively, critics sometimes claim that if private provision were actually better it would have already prevailed, conveniently ignoring the various ways in which the government has outlawed or burdened private provision, to destroy or cripple private competition with the state.
Even ostensibly impartial commentators
generally lean toward placing the burden of proof on those who challenge the
status quo, whether the dispute arises in science, politics, public policy, or
any other domain in which an orthodoxy reigns or long-established institutions
operate. This bias has a strongly conservative force in the sense that
it helps to preserve whatever has gained sway, regardless of how it
attained its current domination. Thus, replacement of the geocentric model of
planetary motion in the solar system with the heliocentric model required
more than a century. Copernicus, Galileo, Newton, and others had to
adduce proof that their conception was superior to the Ptolemaic model, which
was taken to be correct mainly by virtue of its having been accepted for a
very long time.
Likewise, the modern nation-state
has been a well established institution for hundreds of years, during which it
has tended to expand its size, scope, and power, ultimately achieving its
current near-totalitarian form. People living now are accustomed to what the
state is and what it does, and they have difficulty in imagining how
alternative arrangements might operate at all, much less how they might operate
much more successfully for the general public. Hence, ordinary politics takes
the form of arguments and policies that move the state back and forth between
the 5 yard line and the 4 yard line, not far from the goal line of
totalitarianism. The libertarians who propose to move the state back to the 50
yard line, or even to move it all the way to the opposite goal line
of statelessness, have difficulty in gaining a hearing for their
arguments, much less widespread acceptance of their proposals.
The libertarians’ critics
invariably respond that the libertarians are Utopians, that they seek the impossible,
notwithstanding that the modern nation-state did not always exist and that
the hopes widely placed in the current nation-state—an institutional
arrangement born in and sustained by periodic mass murder and continuous
extortion and robbery—testify to a genuinely Utopian mindset. People dismiss
the panoply of state crimes as aberrations or they adduce ad hoc explanations,
rather than face the fact that across the extremely diverse times and places
where unspeakably horrible large-scale crimes have been committed, the
state has been the common denominator.
Like Winston Churchill, who
famously quipped that democracy is the worst form of government except for all
of the others, most people now presume—without seriously bearing a burden of
proof—that the existing state system is superior to all the others. The
libertarian has a right to demand: show me. Give me an organized, rational,
fact-based argument, not simply the flippant dismissal that I am a
dreamer. Copernicus, Galileo, and Newton were widely viewed as dreamers in
their day, too.
Morally speaking, it would seem
that those who opt in favor of coercive arrangements ought to bear the burden
of proof. If the state is such a superior arrangement, by comparison with
genuine, voluntary self-government, why must the state be propped up by
all of its police and armed forces? Why must people be constantly threatened
with imprisonment and death in order to bring forth the revenues that support
the state’s activities? Walmart does not put a gun to my head to gain my
patronage.
Of course, the standard
mainstream-economics apology for this threat of violence against unwilling
purchasers is that government provides a “public good” and hence must cope with
a consequent “free rider” incentive to avoid payment. The trouble is that very
little, if any, of what modern governments provide satisfies the criteria
for categorization as a public good. The payments the government gives grandma
in her pension are not a public good, nor are the payments that compensate doctors
and hospitals for grandpa’s medical care, nor are the payments that purchase
teachers and buildings to educate my neighbor’s kids (while I homeschool my
own), and on and on. The “national defense” that serves as the usual example of
a government-supplied public good is in fact a ludicrously poor example.
Many of us wish the armed forces would cease their current activities in
stirring up trouble for Americans around the world, killing innocent people,
and destroying property in the service of the military-industrial-congressional
complex. I would voluntarily pay to make these hired killers stop what they are
doing, come home, and take up honest employment. Some public good!
In truth, the state occupies
itself massively in snatching private wealth, transferring much of it to
favored supporters, wasting a great deal of it, and retaining the balance to
pay its own legions of bullies, do-gooders, and time-servers, as well as
its palace guard of police and military forces. This whole vile apparatus has
no claim to self-evident superiority to alternative arrangements; it ought to
bear the burden of proof for every step it takes; and we ought to recognize
that the blackboard proofs proffered by mainstream economists, which compose
so-called modern welfare economics, will not feed the baby. This entire body of
thought ought to be dismissed as more a corpus of apologetics than a serious
attempt to justify the state’s pervasively invasive actions in modern life.
Much more might be said along
these lines, of course, but enough has been said, I hope, to make the case that
placement of the burden of proof is utterly crucial in the resolution of
disputes, whether they be in science, public policy, or economic analysis.
Moreover, we need to be constantly aware that if an arrangement depends on
violence or the threat of violence to keep it afloat, it almost
certainly has severe deficiencies. Raw force is always the resort of
someone who cannot present a persuasive argument in support of his actions.
Although the modern state enjoys the support of countless court intellectuals
and apologists, it rests firmly on violence in the event that we do not accept
the excuses it makes for its crimes. That so many of us fear and loathe the
state should in itself be sufficient to indicate that the state, not those of
us who long for freedom, should always bear the burden of proof.
No comments:
Post a Comment