by DETLEV SCHLICHTER
For a long time I considered myself a classical liberal – as did Ludwig von
Mises who inspired much of my work. I do no longer think that this position is
logically consistent. The classical liberal position, although advocating a
much smaller state than today’s political consensus, still assigns too many
powers to the state. Nevertheless, it offers a good starting point for the
discussion. So let us start here.
Utilitarian arguments for the strictly limited state
The classical liberal position on the role of the state can approximately
be described as follows: The state should stay completely out of the economy.
There is no role for the state in industry, banking or money. Money is gold, or
any other commodity chosen by the trading public. The supply of money is thus
outside of political control, and banking and finance are entirely free market
businesses with no state support, no guarantee nor any explicit or implicit
backstops.
Additionally, all means of production are privately owned and their use is directed by market prices, and by the opportunity for profit and the risk of loss. Profit and loss are essential tools for the consumers to direct the activities of private enterprise so that they conform as much as possible to the wishes of the buying public. The state is not involved in education, health care or old age provision or any other so-called social services. All these activities are organized privately for the simple reason that all these activities require the use of scarce resource, including labor, and any rational allocation of scarce resources requires market prices. Only on the basis of market prices is rational economic planning possible. Only market prices convey the urgency that the public assigns to the various competing ends to which resources can be put at each point in time. But market prices can only be determined if the resources are privately owned and traded on free markets. Private property is thus the essential tool for extensive social co-operation. Private property allows trade and the formation of market prices. This then allows the rational and efficient employment of these resources by entrepreneurs. The whole process is the only one logically possible to facilitate an extensive division of labor and the constant accumulation of capital employed in private enterprise, and it is the system of extensive division of labor and the constant accumulation of capital that makes our high living standards and any further advances in living standards possible.
An example:
Britain’s National Health Service will never deliver a satisfactory
service. This is not because the people who work in it are incompetent or lazy.
They could be the most motivated, devoted and well-meaning people on the planet
and they could still only deliver suboptimal results and do so at considerable
cost. Why? Because the NHS has to deliver health services for an entire nation
without the help of true market prices and profit and loss accounting. These
are the tools of capitalism that – day in and day out – allow the private
sector to make informed decisions about best resource use – ‘informed’ because
reflecting the preferences and wishes of the customers, the consumers.
Despite the widespread sentimental attachment to the NHS and its
superficially appealing motto of delivering health care “free of charge”
(obviously not true for the majority of citizens), the fundamental shortcomings
of any service organized along socialist lines should be glaringly obvious to
anyone: While the still fairly unrestricted private mobile phone industry in
Britain delivers the latest advances in telecommunications technology to people
across the entire social spectrum with remarkable speed and at constantly
falling prices, the nationalized health service bureaucracy has people wait in
line even for many routine and long-established procedures and provides such
service at ever more staggering cost to the taxpayer.
That health service
and education are too important to be left to the private market is a common
prejudice that puts economic logic on its head: Because they are important they
should be allowed to employ the tools of the private market.
But what does that mean for those who are too poor or for whatever reason
unable to obtain the market income to afford themselves even a minimum of these
services? – I am not going to evade that question. It is, of course, a standard
response. I will come back to it a bit later.
What does the argument so far mean for the size and role of the state? –
The state would, of course, be rather small by today’s standard. It would only
have one function: to protect private property, which necessarily includes
property in ourselves. The state’s role would be to protect every citizen and
his or her property from aggression, whether that aggression comes from inside
the country or outside the country. The state would be reduced to what the
German social democrats of the late 19th century
derogatorily but still accurately called the ‘night-watchman state’. The state
would provide security services, including police, army, courts and related
services. Its only function would be to provide security and protection.
Those citizens who do not transgress against other peoples’ person or
property or those who are not being transgressed against, would hardly ever
come into contact with the state and its representatives. This would indeed be
a minimal state.
Thus far, we have argued on the basis of utilitarian considerations. A
prosperous society requires high degrees of division of labor and efficient
resource use, which in turn require market prices, which in turn require
private property. Under utilitarianism, private property is first and foremost
a social convention, a means to an end. And the function of the state is to
secure this means: private property, the existence of every individual’s
inviolable private domain, as the basis for voluntary contractual cooperation
and the spontaneous growth of society.
Ethical arguments for the strictly limited state
But such a minimal state can also be constructed on ethical grounds and
considerations of justice. Every state is an institution that is based on
compulsion and coercion. It can be seen as a depository of legalized,
institutionalized and regulated force or threat of force. But what type of
force is ethically defendable and could therefore provide an acceptable
conceptual basis for institutionalized force? Only defensive or protective
force fulfils that requirement.
To answer questions of ethics we need to start with the acting individual.
In an otherwise peaceful, cooperative society, at what point am I justified to
apply force or the threat of force when dealing with other people? Only if and
when these people threaten my life, health or my property. This does not mean
that any type of violent response is deemed justified in such situations, but
it is clear that if force and violence can be justified at all, it must be in
situations of self-defense, which include defense of property. If I am
justified to defend myself from attack, I must also be allowed to defend those
material goods that I have obtained through my work by applying my own body and
mind. If this were not the case and if others were allowed to avail themselves
of the fruits of my labor by simply taking them from me it would mean they could
live off my work and thus practically enslave me, which would be equivalent to
an attack on my person.
By transferring the individual’s right to self-protection and self-defense
of life and property to a specialized organization that fulfils the task of
looking after these rights for all members of the community, no new special
rights have come into existence. It is not claimed that the state has any
rights or powers that the individual citizen does not have already. In fact,
the state’s legalized force would have its origin in a concept of natural
rights that originate with the individual citizen and that that citizen would
have even in a stateless society (although in such a society he would have to
enforce these rights himself or in voluntary cooperation with others). The
state could perhaps be thought of as a pooling of these individual rights to
allow for their more organized, standardized and thus more predictable
safeguarding.
The utilitarian case against the welfare state
We can now turn to the question of provision for poor citizens or for those
who for any reason are unable to adequately support themselves. While good
arguments can be made that those in society who are better off have moral
obligations to give support to weaker members of society, it is clear from the
reasoning above that the state should not enforce such support. Again, the
state is an organization that operates through compulsion and coercion. By
assuming ‘social’ responsibilities the state must redistributes income and
property on an ongoing basis by application of force or the threat of force,
and must thus be permanently in violation of its original mission, which was to
protect rightfully gained private property from violent interference, and thus
support the institution of private property that we identified as absolutely
essential for any functioning society. The state cannot simply add a
redistribution function to its property protection function – the former must
always violate the latter. Both functions stand in logical conflict. Either the
state is a property-protector or a property-re-distributor and
property–re-allocator. The state cannot be both at the same time.
In the original concept of the state as organized force for the purpose of security provision, a person who rightfully obtained property through production or voluntary exchange with other members of the community should be able to rely on the state to protect his ownership from any violation by a third party. But the moment the state assumes any responsibilities for ‘social justice’ or ‘distributive justice’, the state has to become a private property invader itself, and every person has to fear that parts of their income and property – although lawfully obtained – will be taken by the state by force and reallocated to other members of the community.
It is clear that under a state that assumes ‘social’ responsibilities, any
right to private property is ultimately conditional. Rights to property are
only protected by the state as long as the state does not consider third
parties more in need and morally more worthy of ownership of the property.
Every piece of property in such a society is therefore under a cloud of
uncertainty, and this stands in direct conflict to the original mission of the
state. The element of uncertainty is magnified by the fact that while it is
possible to lay down clear and universal rules for how property can be
rightfully and legally obtained, and to therefore give every member of society
clear rules that are knownbefore the act
of what constitutes rightful and what constitutes unlawful attainment of
property, any notion of what constitutes ‘distributive justice’ after the acts of production and trade must
necessarily be arbitrary and subject to considerable change over time. It
should not be surprising that all states have greatly expanded their range of
redistributive policies and social legislation and regulation in recent
decades. Once the state has taken it upon itself to pursue the logically
non-definable goal of social equality or justice, it can ask for ever more
wide-reaching powers. The idea of a minimal state has now become utterly
unrealistic.
By contrast, any redistribution of property or income through acts of
charity stands in no conflict to the institution of private property. The giver
and the recipient of charity both know who the rightful owner of the property
is. The recipient is aware that he is being supported by the generosity of
others. The giver also retains control over who he wants to support and to what
extent he wants to support that person. All of this changes when the state as
monopolist of legal coercion becomes the middleman. The recipient does no
longer consider himself dependent on the economic success and charity of others
but now has a legal claim on support from the state – receiving support becomes
the person’s legally enforceable right. With at least a minimum of income now
secured, the incentives to change one’s behavior to regain economic
independence are weakened. The original owner of property, meanwhile, has no
longer control over where his money goes and will probably lose any interest in
the plight of those who require support. By having been taxed by the state, he
considers all duties to society’s weaker members fully discharged of.
The defenders of the welfare state will argue that it is more just to
introduce an element of uncertainty into the lives of the economically
independent than to keep society’s weakest members subject to the complete
uncertainty that poverty and dependency on charity inevitably entail. While
this is an appealing argument and probably a widely shared sentiment, it cannot
dispel concerns over the fundamental conflict between securing private property
on the one hand and persistently redistributing private property on the other.
A welfare state is, fundamentally and conceptually, a persistent threat to the
notion of private property, and private property is undeniably the economic
foundation of any society. Additionally, any concept of ‘social justice’ is by
definition arbitrary and will be the source of tremendous strife whenever it is
supposed to guide practical politics. Furthermore, a state that concerns itself
with the distribution of income and property among its citizens will never be a
small state, or even a limited state.
The ethical case against the welfare state
The argument has so far been based on utilitarian considerations. But we
can base it also on theories of ethics and justice. We have argued that a state
that confines itself to the protection of person and property of its citizens
against any unprovoked acts of aggression bases its right to legal force on the
rights to such force by its individual members. The state assumes no privileged
position but simply exercises the rights that the individual citizen already
has but that the citizen may consider to be secured and enforced better through
a state organization. This view, however, is no longer tenable when the state
enforces redistribution of income and property.
While it is certainly within generally accepted principles of justice if I
use proportional force to stop my neighbor from stealing or damaging my
property or from inflicting injury on me or anybody in my family, it is
certainly outside the established norms of justice if I decided to force my
neighbor to support third parties, chosen by me, who I think are deserving of
my neighbor’s support. By making ‘social justice’ its goal, the state claims a
right to legal force that none of its citizens has. The state has now become a
law upon itself, a ‘higher’ entity whose standards of right and wrong no longer
correspond to those of its individual citizens. Any idea that the state could
simply represent a convenient and efficient pooling of individual rights for
the purpose of their better protection is now untenable. The state can do and
does what nobody outside the state can do. The state qua state defines its own
notions of morality and forces them upon its citizens.
We have now explained why any state that assumes larger responsibilities
than the minimal state which confines itself to articulating, clarifying and
enforcing the rights of its individual citizens to their own life and property
must be in violation of its citizens’ rights to their own life and property and
can no longer justify its existence on the based of any ‘social contract’, for
such a contract can only ever encompass the rights that individuals already
have and which they may then voluntarily transfer to the state entity as part
of entering such a contract. We have also seen that a state that gets involved
in the distribution of income and property among its citizens must undermine
the institution of private property, which is essential for human cooperation
in a market economy and the basis of any prosperous society.
From classical liberalism to anarcho-libertarianism
While such a minimal state – a pure protector of life and property of its
citizens, an enforcer of laws and a provider of courts to facilitate the
resolution of conflicts and the further development of the laws – would be a
much better guarantor of individual liberty and of peaceful cooperation than
today’s heavily interventionist, constantly meddling and increasingly
authoritarian state, and while most libertarians today would be happy to see a
return to this classical liberal vision of the minimal state, even this concept
is still flawed for as long as the organization that calls itself a state
claims to have a territorial monopoly on providing protection and security
services and a monopoly of ultimate decision making in its territory (this is
in fact a very good definition of the state by Hans-Hermann Hoppe). If the
state not only uses legal force to protect life and property of its citizens
but if the state, as all states presently do, uses force to stop citizens from
voluntarily exiting the state’s framework and establishing or joining different
and competing arrangements on its territory, then we will have to also reject
this minimal state on the basis of the analysis above.
First, again, are utilitarian considerations. Providing security services
also necessitates the use of scare resources. How many resources are to be
allocated to providing security, which resources should be used and to what
extent, are essential questions. Without private property, market prices and
free entry into the market of security provision, the results will again be far
from optimal. Even in the area of security provision market-based solutions are
undoubtedly superior. This important argument was first developed by the 19th century Belgian economist, Gustave de
Molinari.
Second, we have considerations of ethics and justice. If the state claims
to derive its legitimacy to use force from the individual citizen’s right to
use force to defend his own life and property, this must mean that the
individual’s rights are the origin of the state’s rights, and that the latter
can never supercede the former. To put this differently, a state that claims a
territorial monopoly on security provision and conflict resolution must argue
that the individual who had the right to use force for defense of life and
property in the first place has, by pooling these rights into a state-like organization,
now forfeited these rights forever and is not to be permitted to reclaim these
rights and enforce them by alternative means. This is logically an untenable
position.
It seems fair to assume that law and security provision have a lot in
common with money in that they, too, are subject to network effects. Just as
the co-existence of many parallel monies is suboptimal, the co-existence of
many different legal frameworks and security arrangements is inefficient. But
none of this means that individuals have not the right to make alternative
arrangements if they deem present arrangements to be insufficient or even a
threat to their own life and property. We conclude that at a very minimum the
minimal state must concede a universal and inviolable right of every individual
or group of individuals to secede at any time.
A lot of what I argued above may appear to many like idle libertarian
theorizing with little relevance to present political reality. But a crisis of
the present state fiat money system is now inevitable. This crisis is part of a
broader crisis of the welfare state and, in fact, of democracy. As these crises
unfold, people will again revisit some fundamental questions about the size and
role of the state and its relationship to the individual. Against this
backdrop, discussions like this one could become very relevant indeed. As
states everywhere go broke, as the promises of the cradle-to-grave welfare
state are defaulted on, and as politicians lose control over their
overstretched fiat money empires, citizens will again consider looking for and
establishing more suitable and functioning alternatives to present state
apparatuses.
I will finish this easy with a short extract from Lysander Spooner’s
outstanding pamphlet No Treason, NO II from 1867, in which he delivers a fascinating
interpretation of the American constitution that is an excellent presentation
of the points I was trying to make toward the end of the above essay. Here is
Spooner:
“The Constitution says:
‘We, the people of the United States, in order to form a more perfect union, establish justice, insure domestic tranquility, provide for the common defense, promote the general welfare, and secure the blessings of liberty to ourselves and our posterity, do ordain and establish this Constitution for the United States of America.’
The meaning of this is simply: We, the people of the United States,acting freely and voluntarily as individuals, consent and agree that
we will cooperate with each other in sustaining such a government as is
provided for in this Constitution.
The necessity for the consent of “the people” is implied in this
declaration. The whole authority of the Constitution rests
upon it. If they did not consent, it was of no validity. Of course it had no
validity, except as between those who actually consented. No one’s
consent could be presumed against him, without his actual consent being given,
any more than in the case of any other contract to pay money, or render
service. And to make it binding upon any one, his signature, or other positive
evidence of consent, was as necessary as in the case of any other contract. If
the instrument meant to say that any of “the people of the United States” would
be bound by it, who did not consent, it was a usurpation and a lie. The most
that can be inferred from the form, “We, the people,” is,
that the instrument offeredmembership to all “the people of the United States;” leaving it
for them to accept or refuse it, at their pleasure.
The agreement is a simple one, like any other agreement. It is the same as
one that should say: We, the people of the town of A━━, agree to sustain a church, a school, a hospital, or a theatre, for
ourselves and our children.
Such an agreement clearly could have no validity, except as between those
who actually consented to it. If a portion only of “the people of the town of A━━,” should assent to this contract, and should then proceed to compel contributions of money or service from
those who had not consented, they would be mere robbers; and would deserve to
be treated as such.
Neither the conduct nor the rights of these signers would be improved at
all by their saying to the dissenters: We offer you equal rights with
ourselves, in the benefits of the church, school, hospital, or theatre, which
we propose to establish, and equal voice in the control of it. It would be a
sufficient answer for the others to say: We want no share in the benefits, and
no voice in the control of your institution; and will do nothing to support
it.”
No comments:
Post a Comment