By Tibor R. Machan
No one should attempt to treat Ayn
Rand and Murray N. Rothbard as uncomplicated and rather similar defenders of
the free society although they have more in common than many believe. As just
one example, neither was a hawk when it comes to deploying military power
abroad. There is evidence, too, that both considered it imprudent for the US
government to be entangled in international affairs, such as fighting dictators
who were no threat to America. Even their lack of enthusiasm for entering WW II
could be seen as quite similar.
And so far as their underlying
philosophical positions are concerned, they both can be regarded as
Aristotelians. In matters of economics they were unwavering supporters of the
fully free market capitalist system, although while Rand didn’t find
corporations per se objectionable, arguably Rothbard had some problems with
corporate commerce, especially as it manifest itself in the 20th century. One
sphere in which they took very different positions, at least at first glance,
is whether government is a bona fide feature of a genuinely free country. Rand
thought it is, Rothbard thought it wasn’t. Yet the reason Rothbard opposed
government was that it depended on taxation, something Rand also opposed, so
even here where the difference between them appears to be quite stark, they
were closer than one might think.
When intellectuals such as Rand and
Rothbard have roughly the same political-economic position, it isn’t that
surprising that they and their followers would stress the difference between
them instead of the similarities. Moreover, in this case both had a similar
explosive personality, with powerful likes and dislikes not just in
fundamentals but also in what may legitimately be considered incidentals–music,
poetry, novels, movies and so forth.
Yet what for Rothbard might be something tangential, even incidental, to his political economic thought, for Rand could be considered more germane since Rand thought of herself–and many think of her–as a philosopher (roughly of the rank of a Herbert Spencer or Auguste Comte). Rothbard wrote little in the sphere of metaphysics and epistemology, although he was well informed in these branches of philosophy, while Rand chimed in, quite directly, on several philosophical issues, having written what amounts to a rather nuanced long philosophical essay on epistemology and advanced ideas in metaphysics, such as on free will, causality, and the nature of universals. Her followers, such as Nathaniel Bradnen, Leonard Peikoff, Tara Smith, Alan Gotthelf, James Lennox, and David Kelley, among others, have all made contributions to serious discussions in various branches of philosophy.
The central dispute, however,
between Rothbard and his followers and Rand and hers focuses, as I have already
noted, on whether a free country would have a government. The debate is moved
forward in the volume edited by Roderick Long and me, Anarchism versus
Minarchism; Is Government Part of a Free County (Ashgate, 2006).
Even apart from their disagreement
about the justifiability of government in a bona fide free country, there is
the difference between them about the subjectivity of (some) values. Rothbard
holds, for example, that “’distribution’ is simply the result of the free
exchange process, and since this process benefits all participants on the
market and increases social utility, it follows directly that the
‘distributional’ results of the free market also increase social utility.” The
part here that shows the difference between Rothbard and Rand is where Rothbard
says that the “free exchange process … benefits all participants on the
market.” Maybe most of them benefit in such exchanges do but some do not.
Suppose someone exchanges five ounces of crack cocaine for an ounce of heroin.
Arguably, at least as Ayn Rand would very likely maintain, neither of these
traders gains a benefit in this exchange, assuming that both commodities being
trade are objectively harmful to the traders’ health. Both are, then, harmed,
objectively speaking, even if they believed they would benefit.
This may be a minor matter but it
isn’t, not at least if Rothbard’s idea is generalized to apply to all market
exchanges. True, from a purely economic viewpoint both parties in free
exchanges tend to take it or believe that they are benefited by these. But this
belief could well be false.
Now of course Rand would agree with
Rothbard that just because people engage in trade that’s harmful to them, it
doesn’t follow that anyone, least of all the government, is authorized to ban
such trade or otherwise interfere with it. Such matters as what may or may not
harm free market traders from the trades they choose to engage in are supposed
to be dealt with in the private sector. Family, friends, doctors, nurses, et
al., or other agents devoted to advising people what they should and should not
do are the only ones who may launch peaceful educational or advisory measures
to remedy the private misjudgments and misconduct of peaceful market
participants. Such an approach sees public policies such as the war on drugs as
entirely unjustified even if consuming many drugs is objectively damaging to
those doing so.
In any case, the Randian view
doesn’t assume that all free trade benefits those embarking on them. Let me,
however, return to the major bone of contention between Murray Rothbard and Ayn
Rand, namely, whether government is (or could be) part of a free country. Given
that Rothbard believes government cannot exists without deploying the
rights-violating policy of taxation, his view is understandable but the underlying
assumption that gives rise to it is questionable. Rand did indeed question it
in her discussion of funding government in the chapter “Government Financing in
a Free society” in The Virtue of Selfishness, at least by implication, when she
argued that government can be financed without taxation. If she is correct,
then Rothbard or his followers need to mount a different attack on the idea
that the free society can have a government. (And some have indeed made this
argument, including me in, for example, my “Anarchism and Minarchism, A
Rapprochement,” Journal des Economists et des Estudes Humaines, Vol. 14, No. 4
[December 2002], 569-588.)
Rand proposed that instead of
taxation, which involves the rights-violating policy of confiscation of private
property, a government could be funded by way of a contract fee, a lottery, or
some other peaceful method. Whether this is so cannot be addressed here but it
shows that Rand and Rothbard were not very distant from each other on the issue
of the justifiability of government in a free country. Perhaps the term
“government” is ill advised when applied to whatever kind of law-enforcement
institution would be involved in bona fide free countries. But this is not
what’s crucial–a rose by any other name is still a rose and a law-enforcement,
judicial or defense agency in a free society is what is at issue here, not what
term is used to call it. So, again, Rand and Rothbard seem closer than usually
believed.
Yet it’s not just about taxation for
many who follow Rothbard. Most also hold that the idea is mistaken that
government–or whatever it is called–needs to serve a society occupying a
continuous instead of Swiss cheese like region. The idea of a
disparately located country, without a continuous territory and with the
possibility of all parts being accessible by law enforcers without the need of
international treaties, makes sense to Rothbardians. Not, however, to Randians,
it can be argued, not unless the familiar science fiction transportation option
of being “beamed up” from one area to anther (so that law enforcement can reach
all those within its jurisdiction) is available. Otherwise enforcement of the
law can be easily evaded by criminals.
Again, this isn’t the place to
resolve the dispute between Rand & her followers and Rothbard and his. This
brief discussion should, however, indicate where their differences lie. It
doesn’t at all explain, however, why the different parties to the debate tend
often to be quite acrimonious toward each other. What may explain this, though,
is a simple point of psychology. Nearly all champions of a fully free,
libertarian society are also avid individualists and often tend to insist on
what might be called the policy: My way or the highway! Even when their
differences don’t warrant it.
No comments:
Post a Comment