by Frank Chodorov
The techniques of the market
place evolve from man's unceasing drive toward a richer and fuller life. One
technique that plays a most important part in this general purpose is
competition, or the vying among the specialists for the favor of the community.
Although the competitors are motivated by self-interest, each one seeking the
custom of his fellow men, the effect of the rivalry is to bring an abundance
into the market place, to the greater benefit of Society. To win favor for his
offerings, as against the offerings of others in the same line, each competitor
tries to improve his capacity for production, as to quantity or quality; each seeks
to better his competence.
But, what is competence, and how is it determined by those whose trade is sought? Getting down to the bedrock of definitions, competence is a grade of performance, and as the word is generally used it designates a high grade. Its opposite is incompetence, a low grade, and in between there must be a number of gradations. A performance is good or bad, competent or incompetent, only in comparison with other performances.
But, what is competence, and how is it determined by those whose trade is sought? Getting down to the bedrock of definitions, competence is a grade of performance, and as the word is generally used it designates a high grade. Its opposite is incompetence, a low grade, and in between there must be a number of gradations. A performance is good or bad, competent or incompetent, only in comparison with other performances.
If Smith is the only cobbler
in town, and we are unacquainted with the workmanship of cobblers in other
towns, how can we judge his skill? The best we can do under the circumstances
is to compare his performance with what we could do for ourselves as amateur
cobblers; before he came, that was the best service we had. Let us concede that
our monopoly cobbler is a decent fellow and that he does the best he can for
our footwear. But he is under no compulsion to do better, and his best may be
determined by his conscience or the state of his health. Like the rest of us,
he dislikes the irksomeness and weariness of toil and tries to get by with the
minimum of effort. Since we cannot take our trade elsewhere, and Smith is aware
of this, his natural inclination is to take a let-well-enough-alone attitude
toward his workmanship, and in fixing his prices he follows the rule of
"all the traffic will bear." The only restraint on his monopoly
impulse is the possibility of driving his customers to self-help cobbling and
losing their trade.
The practical measurement of
competence is the profit-and-loss statement of the competitor, for in it are
recorded the favorable or unfavorable votes of the Society he serves. Thus, the
income of the auto mechanic reflects the repairs he has effected, the profits
of the manufacturer prove his ability to produce what is wanted, the salary of
the managerial genius comes off the production line. Each has been rewarded by
Society for his performance, as compared with the performances of his
competitors, and his gain is proof enough that Society has gained. It follows
then that a Society of affluent competitors is one in which the wage level, or
the general fund of satisfactions, is high.
The coming of Brown may be a
benefit to the community, but to Smith it is a discomfit. Heretofore, his
craftsmanship and the price he charged for his service were fixed by his own
convenience, but now he is compelled to meet standards set by another. The
monopoly impulse in him, which he shares with all human beings, is disturbed.
Therefore, Smith is inclined to prevent Brown from offering his competitive
service to his trade and under primitive conditions might resort to arms. Since
a growing Society frowns upon such crude methods, he turns to a more
sophisticated use of force, that of convincing his neighbors that scarcity in
some way improves their lot; that "home industry" should be
encouraged; that Brown is an inferior human being and therefore a detriment to
the community; that lower prices endanger the "general economy."
Perhaps his argument is convincing because each of his neighbors entertains the
hope of a monopoly position of his own, of getting something for nothing; at
any rate, he succeeds in using collective force to achieve his private purpose.
And thus come scarcity-producing laws, such as protective tariffs, exclusion
acts, prohibitions on labor-saving devices, restraints on trade, or a tax on
enterprise. Either Brown is prevented from offering his services to the
community, or his goods are kept out of the market place, or a tax is levied on
his improved machinery — or maybe a labor union prevents him from using it. It
is by force that Smith retains his comfortable monopoly position; it is by
force that competition is prevented from enriching the market place.
It is an odd circumstance that
such scarcity-producing measures are not self-enforcing, simply because the
monopoly impulse is counterbalanced by the stronger urge of the human for
abundance, and the conflict results in lawbreaking by the very law passers.
Thus comes the practice of smuggling, of tax evasion, of bootlegging, as well
as the resort to substitutes for the product made scarce by monopoly. It is not
surprising that Smith's neighbors, who helped him avoid competition, avail
themselves by devious methods of Brown's services.
When a monopoly position is
achieved, when competition is eliminated or restrained, competence has a new
meaning. It no longer designates a standard of performance fixed in the market
place. The monopolist, the one who controls the supply of a desirable commodity
or service, regulates his performance by a neat formula: the highest price
which will yield him the highest net profit. If he increases the output beyond
a predetermined point, he must lower the price so as to induce greater
consumption, and nothing is gained. If he increases the price, consumption will
fall and so will his net profit. Competence in a monopoly therefore consists in
finding (by the trial-and-error method) the exact profit-yielding ratio between
price and performance. The profit-and-loss statement of a monopoly business
reflects only in part the service it has rendered Society; it also includes an
exaction price made possible by the scarcity it is able to cause.[1]
The key to monopoly is
scarcity. Some scarcities are natural, such as mineral deposits and land sites;
there is no way for humans to duplicate them. The ownership or control of these
limited opportunities to produce enables the monopolist to exact a rent price
for the use of them. The rent price is fixed by their relative scarcity — or by
the yield of any given site over that of any other site available to use. In
point of fact, the rent price is fixed by competition among users or producers
for exclusive possession of these locations.
Other scarcities are made by
law, and the mechanism by which these scarcities are effected is always a
coercive restriction on competition. Although the restrictive measures are
sometimes concocted by individuals or groups in search of a monopoly price, these
are of little effect unless and until they are implemented with the strong arm
of the law, as when it imposes trade regulations, tries to fix prices,
subsidizes inefficient producers at the expense of efficient ones, enables
labor organizations to put limits on enterprise, or grants special privileges
to favored individuals. This brings us to a consideration of the part played by
the political organization of Society in its economy, which we must leave to a
later chapter. For the present, we leave the matter with this observation:
there cannot be an effective blocking of man's urge for abundance through
competition without the aid of the law. That is, every scarcity-making device
rests on political coercion.
Indeed, those who decry
competition on pseudohumanitarian grounds look to the law to restrain
competition, even as they call upon the law to prevent the monopoly exactions
made possible by such restraint. Their argument is that those who are possessed
of less ability are handicapped in the competitive struggle and will be hurt
unless the more competent are shackled. (Sometimes they urge the discouragement
of initiative by proposing that the profits which bring out initiative be taxed
away, sometimes they contemplate the impossible task of rooting out the profit
motive altogether.) But how can any member of Society be hurt by an abundance
in the market place? If Brown, because of his greater skill or industry, takes
shoe business away from Smith, his success is proof that he has rendered a
greater service to the members of the community; they are the better off
because of his efficiency. He has produced better shoes, or a greater variety
of styles and sizes, or through improved methods has lowered his costs and
reduced prices. But his efficiency is meaningless unless they buy his shoes;
buying his shoes means that they have produced something he wants. That is to
say, any increase in the production of one desirable thing calls for the
production of other desirable things. In the case of Brown, his burgeoning shoe
business necessitates the production of more shoe findings, shoe boxes, and
other incidentals, to say nothing of stimulating such services as
transportation, book-keeping, selling; furthermore, he must employ more people
in his operation. In this profusion of activity, Smith is sure to find a
remunerative occupation of some kind, and though his pride may suffer because
he had not been able to keep up with the standard set by Brown, his well-being
may have been improved. The old adage has it that "competition is good for
business," and when business is "good" all Society prospers.
The anticompetition advocates
like to stress the point that large aggregations of capital put the
"little fellow" at a disadvantage; because of the means at his
disposal the "big fellow" is able to buy raw materials in large
quantities and therefore at a lower price, to put in the most advanced
machinery, to invest in expensive selling campaigns. Quite true. Putting aside
the fact that all this merely means greater production for the benefit of
Society, the record shows that bigness in itself imposes restrictions on
production; the ponderous plant lacks the flexibility necessary to meet the
vagaries of human desire. Brown, the large shoe manufacturer, cannot cater to
the foot that does not conform to some norm or to the whims of the fastidious
wearer. His plant is geared to mass production. It is Smith, who either did not
choose to become a manufacturer or was not adapted for the role, who must serve
this clientele, which always grows in proportion to the increase of wealth in
the community; the number of small plants or "specialty shops" keeps
pace with the number and size of large industrial units. In fact, the large
plant admits its limitations when it turns over to its smaller competitor the
jobs it cannot do as efficiently.
There is nothing wrong with
competition that competition cannot cure. The faults of competition are in the
impediments that are put in its way by force — the restraints, taxes, and
regulations that handicap some competitors and give others a monopoly or
quasi-monopoly position. Competition serves Society best when it is free. In
the field of cultural satisfactions no one would propose that competition be
shackled, that the better singer be compelled to perform under poorer acoustic
conditions than those afforded the second-rater, or that the discrepancies in
artistic ability be equalized by law. There is common agreement that in those
occupations the impartial verdict of the market place is final, even if it
decides that the inferior ballplayer would better serve Society, and himself,
by driving a truck. Since the expectation of material rewards (the profit
motive) plays a big part in stimulating desirable competition among these
cultural specialists, it should follow that competition among those engaged in
the production of material things is equally desirable. The artist also seeks
to satisfy his desires with the minimum of effort.
On the score of
humanitarianism, free competition commends itself on the ground that those who
are necessarily outside the field of production, or partly so, are in better
case in an economy of plenty than in an economy of scarcity. The physically
handicapped, the children, and the aged must in any event be taken care of, and
their lot is better in a household where the pantry is full.
To repeat, this does not
pretend to be a book on economics. It is rather an attempt to show that
economics plays a big, if not major, part in the formation and development of
social integrations and institutions, and toward that end it was necessary to
outline, broadly, the economic principles which bear upon the thesis.
Any inquiry into the nature of
or reason for Society (and its attendant political institutions) must begin
with an examination of its integer, the individual. Any other approach would be
like starting in mid-air. But the individual proves to be a rather complicated
phenomenon, with variable and elusive characteristics, casting a variegated
light on his social habits. We must put these aside and seek in the evidence of
his behavior, throughout history and wherever we find him, a constant pattern.
This, and there can be no question about it, is his life-long preoccupation
with the making of a living. His will to live compels him to be the
"economic man." Even the nonmaterial facets of his makeup —
metaphysical, cultural, and spiritual — are in one manner or another tied in
with the way he goes about making his living. The constancy of his concern with
economics indicates that it must be the foundation on which he builds his
social environment; all else is superstructure.
Society, then, is basically an
economic phenomenon. It is an aggregation of individuals who, by means of the
techniques emerging from cooperation, better their circumstances. It is a means
of raising the general wage level; if it did not effect that result it would
tend to disintegrate. The social integrations we call primitive are those in
which the economic techniques have not been developed, for one reason or
another, while the advanced Society is one that exploits them as fully as the
cooperators know how. A perfect Society, or one as perfect as human knowledge
can make it, would be one where these techniques, collectively called the
market place, operated without friction; this, the world has not yet seen, for
reasons that will be explored in the following chapters.
Notes
[1] The competitor, like the
monopolist, seeks the highest price which will yield him the highest net
profit. But, because he is unable to control supply, and thus induce a
scarcity, his highest price is what competition will allow him to charge, which
is always lower than what he would like. In a competitive business, the net
profit breaks down to interest on investment, replacement of capital, and the
wages of superintendence. Only in a monopoly business is there a "little
extra.
No comments:
Post a Comment