Gay marriage is presented as an issue of equal rights, but it’s better understood as a top-down overhaul of the institution of marriage.
by Frank Furedi
Today, there are continuous disputes over moral issues – abortion,
sexuality, euthanasia – yet the ideal of marriage retains a formidable
influence over society.
It is true that
this ideal is frequently contradicted by people’s behaviour. Britain is now at
a point where people are more likely to co-habit than get married. Almost half
of new births occur outside of marriage. With spectacularly high rates of
divorce and a rise in single-parent households, it would appear that marriage
has lost its status as a fundamental institution of society. And yet marriage
as an ideal still dominates the cultural imagination. Most
people look upon marriage as an institution that deserves society’s support,
and also as a model that they aspire to embrace.
You can see the power of this ideal in the way that public figures go out of their way to promote the fact that they are married. Throughout the Western world, political candidates advertise their marital status and their reproductive achievements alongside their policies, as if their identity as a successful husband/father or wife/mother should help them win over the electorate.
The paradox of the idealisation of marriage coexisting with concern about its decline has been a feature of public debate for almost two centuries. By the nineteenth century it was evident that the meaning of marriage had changed and that it was in danger of becoming a caricature of itself. Emile Durkheim, one of the founders of the field of sociology, believed the main function of marriage was ‘to regulate the life of passion, and monogamic marriage more strictly than any other’. He argued that by ‘forcing a man to attach himself forever to the same woman, [marriage] assigns a strictly definite object to the need for love, and closes the horizon’. Durkheim’s emphasis on the role of marriage as a form of social and moral regulation was partly motivated by his fear that, left to their own devices, people might become disoriented, leading to ‘disturbance, agitation and discontent’.
He was
particularly concerned about the legalisation of divorce, which he said implied
a ‘weakening of matrimonial regulation’. He concluded that ‘where it exists’
marriage is ‘nothing but a weakened simulacrum of itself; it is an inferior
form of marriage’ (1). His anxiety about the impact of divorce was underpinned
by his belief that once moral norms become negotiable, there is a disruption to
the fabric of society – and instead of reinforcing cohesion, these newly
disrupted moral norms could undermine it.
Whatever one
thinks of Durkheim’s vision of the moral order, there’s no doubt that his
belief that divorce would transform the institution of marriage was essentially
correct. The right to divorce not only allowed individuals to gain greater
control over their lives; in introducing an element of choice, it also called
into question the taken-for-granted character of marriage itself.
Because of his
preoccupation with the rise of individualism and the potential loss of
restraint, Durkheim one-sidedly emphasised the function of marriage as a
regulator of ‘the life of passion’. Arguably a far more important historical
role of marriage was the management and socialisation of reproduction.
Historically, marriage was not about the regulation of the behaviour and
relationship of two people; rather, it was an institution through
which a community managed the bringing of children to life, the socialising of
children, and the organisation of relationships between generations. This is
the basic core of the institution of marriage. In some communities, this
fundamental role of marriage was supplemented by its role in passing on
property and wealth, controlling women, or establishing alliances and community
cohesion. But whatever the cultural variations, since ancient times marriage
has usually served as an institution of natality, as the model through which
adult responsibility for children is exercised.
Cultures of marriage
Since the
nineteenth century, the moral foundations of Western societies have lost much
of their cohesion. Very few norms and values are beyond question. When
old-fashioned moralists declare, ‘Is nothing sacred anymore?’, my sociologist
self is inclined to answer: ‘Very little.’ The erosion of moral consensus has
had a clear impact on the way that marriage is understood and experienced.
Since the nineteenth century, there have three main moral views of marriage in
Western cultures.
Traditional morality: Sometimes caricatured as ‘Victorian Values’,
this outlook looks upon marriage as essentially a sacred act. The more religious
adherents to traditional morality believe that marriage is an act blessed by
God. It is a singular rite de passage, in the sense that it is
assumed to endure forever. Significantly, a traditional marriage does not only
impact on the behaviour of the newly wedded couple; it also communicates
expectations of how the unmarriedshould live. In this sense, a key
part of its role is to motivate and control the behaviour of the community more
broadly. One reason why marriage still serves as the model for the management
of reproduction is because of its community-wide influence.
Instrumental morality: This is often underpinned by the conventions of
middle-class morality. It tends to regard marriage as a contractual obligation.
Although conventional middle-class marriages are often blessed by a religious
figure, their more distinctive feature is their secular orientation. The
conventional middle-class marriage is based upon a civil contract, which is
legitimated and validated by a government-appointed official. Although such
marriages depict themselves as being ‘for life’, their existence is
increasingly subject to the pragmatic and instrumental concerns of the parties
involved. However, instrumental morality is rarely comfortable with exposing
its calculating orientation towards marriage, and so it often hides behind the
respectable image of tradition.
Individualistic/humanistic morality: This regards
marital attachments as a personal matter, to be negotiated by the people
involved. From this perspective, marriage is a personal matter of choice. What
really matters is the relationship between the couple (the meeting of the
souls) rather than the specific form of the wedding ritual. However, even this
relationship remains under the influence of the basic model of marriage. The
phrase ‘getting married to have children’ is frequently used by these couples,
to explain why they have opted to embrace what remains a traditional
institution. So, unconsciously or semi-consciously, even critics of traditional
or conventional weddings understand that their relationship with their
children, and the relationship between adults and the younger generation more
broadly, is ultimately mediated through the institution of marriage.
It’s all about me, so shut up!
Since Durkheim’s
time, the process of individuation has intensified, further distancing people’s
behaviour and attitudes from traditional and community norms. One of the most
frequently heard songs at weddings and funerals – ‘I did it my way’ – speaks to
the conviction that marriage is really all about me, or occasionally about
‘us’. In such circumstances, the importance of marriage and similar rituals
lies in the way they can be used to help construct an individual’s identity.
In recent decades,
the ascendancy of the politics of identity, which now dominates cultural life,
has had the effect of politicising lifestyle. People now flaunt their identity
and demand respect, valuation and recognition of it.
Since identity
politics is about who we are, it is not open to negotiation. Normal disputes in
public life can be resolved through bargaining and some give-and-take. But an
identity cannot compromise itself without the threat of existential crisis and
isolation. So people who have made a significant emotional investment into
their identity as a ‘yummy mummy’, for example, regard any criticism of
slacking mothers as an attack on them. If a parenting style is
beyond criticism, how can one raise questions about any of the identities
associated with lifestyle, ethnicity, sexuality or family life?
Recently, the
lesbian feminist academic Sheila Jeffreys complained that the ‘criticism of the
practice of transgenderism is being censored as a result of a campaign of vilification
by transgender activists’. Those who ‘do not accept the new orthodoxy’ on
transgender issues are accused of ‘hate speech’. So the idea that
transgenderism is an identity based on sexual fetishism simply cannot be said
anymore. Jeffreys concluded that ‘the effect is to scare off any researchers
from touching the topic’. It’s worse than that: public debate has been scared
off from discussing any of the identities that now have a bearing on marriage,
family life or sexuality.
Sectarian
attitudes towards the politics of identity also dominate the discussion of gay
marriage. Both sides of the debate are dominated by the philosophy ‘It’s all
about me!’. Consequently, there is very little tolerance of open discussion.
So, zealous
advocates of traditional marriage sometimes adopt the language of the
Inquisition, talking of a ‘corrupt gay-union conspiracy’ which aims to
undermine family life and warp children. On the other side, supporters of gay
marriage accuse their critics of ‘bigoted homophobia’ and use shrill language
to attack anyone who criticises their campaign. When the outlook of ‘you’re
either with us or against us’ is dominant in this way, it is difficult to have
a serious public deliberation. These highly moralised narratives are about
shutting down discussion rather than encouraging it.
The sectarian
posturing driving this debate is underpinned by two diametrically opposed
principles: absolutism and relativism. The first upholds the socially
conservative ideal of traditional marriage and unthinkingly rejects the
possibility of any alternative. The latter celebrates gay marriage and
dogmatically rebuffs any attempt to make value judgments about the status of
different forms of unions between two adults. From the standpoint of social
conservatism, only one way of living is right; from the standpoint of
relativist identity politics, the very act of making a moral judgment
represents an insult to certain people.
The current
sectarian exchange on gay marriage carries on where earlier debates on family
life left off. In those discussions, from the 1960s onwards, the ideal of the
traditional family was culturally overwhelmed by the claims of moral
relativism, which suggested that not only is there no longer a single model of
family life but that there should not be one. Where traditionalists criticised
the idea of lifestyle choice, relativistic identity entrepreneurs sought to
demonise anyone who made a judgement about the moral status of various family
set-ups and modern ways of living.
The cultural ascendancy
of moral relativism means that ‘difference’ now enjoys so much cultural
affirmation that it is deemed inappropriate to state a moral preference for one
form of family arrangement over another. One of the first lessons children
learn in schools is that they have a duty to ‘celebrate difference’. This duty
is promoted with a vehemence no less dogmatic than fundamentalist religious
doctrines.
As is the case
with most controversies focused on competing claims for rights, both the
absolutist and relativist approaches fail to do justice to the complexities at
stake.
Legitimate criticisms of gay marriage
As someone who
writes from a liberal and militantly tolerant perspective, I maintain that
there can be a variety of different views on same-sex marriage. Someone with
liberal convictions can argue for gay marriage because he believes that an
individual’s right to self-determination must prevail over all other
considerations. There is also a legitimate liberal argument against gay
marriage, based on the premise that what is at issue is not equality or the
extension of the right to marry but rather the fundamental redefinition of the
institution of marriage. One can argue that this campaign is about reorganising
marriage, reordering the very meaning of marriage, though it is presented as a
struggle for greater equality.
There is a third
liberal argument, which is one that I would propose. Here, we recognise that
individuals ought to have the right to define marriage as they choose, while
asking that this right not be exercised at this point in time.
From the
standpoint of liberalism, gay marriage can be supported on the grounds of
choice but not as a claim to equal rights. And yet, in America the campaign for
gay marriage frequently presents itself as a movement for equality and civil
rights. Some campaigners argue that the denial of same-sex marriage is similar
to the prevention of interracial unions by old segregationist laws.
This association
of marriage with old forms of discrimination represents a manipulation of
historical facts. Segregation was a conscious attempt to exclude or to separate
groups that were deemed to have different racial characteristics. As an
institution, marriage – in all of its forms – was principally oriented towards
the regulation of human reproduction. Not even the most ideologically driven
historian can substantiate the claim that marriage was a heterosexual
conspiracy designed to exclude homosexuals.
The institution of
marriage, in both its ancient and historical variations, has had many
functions, mainly to do with the maintenance and reproduction of society. But
excluding same-sex partners from its purview was not one of them. Today, when
every demand for a new right instantly claims to be the latest reincarnation of
the civil-rights movement, it is easy to forget that, in truth, these demands
are not really about equality.
The only way one
could argue for gay marriage on the grounds of equality is if marriage is
redefined as being less about human reproduction and the preparation of children
for their future as about companionship. That is why all arguments in favour of
gay marriage focus on the right of two people to live in accordance with their
aspirations. This is a legitimate aspiration, of course, but it has little to
do with the institution of marriage; it actually demands a fundamental
redefinition of marriage. Advocates of a companion-based form of marriage have
every right to promote their cause. But it is a cause that does not serve the
interests of equality, but rather the interests of a particular form of
identity. As a believer in tolerance, I have no option but to uphold their
right to choose; but as someone concerned about the consequences of
disorganising an institution that plays a central role in the management of human
reproduction, I am compelled to caution them against exercising this very
misguided choice in the way it is currently proposed.
State out of
marriage
If we take a step
back and recognise that there are different cultures of marriage, then the most
liberal and open-minded way of proceeding is to propose that marriage become a
matter of private preference rather than an institution validated by the state.
So if a group of people or a church insist that they only value weddings that
are traditional and between men and women, then that is their right; they
should not have practices imposed upon them that violate their belief or
conscience. If another group opts for a form of marriage that is open to any
combination of sexes, then they also ought to have the right to wed in
accordance with their beliefs. If marriage is deregulated by the state, then no
one’s ideal need be violated.
State officialdom
is already too involved in family life and the regulation of marriage. One of
the main outcomes of its intervention has been to undermine the authority of
parents and adults over children. Any formal, legal redefinition of marriage –
such as the one being demanded by gay-marriage advocates and their media
supporters – will inexorably strengthen the power of the state over private
life, over how our relationships are defined, understood and experienced.
In previous times,
marriage was a matter for the community rather than the state. We should
recover that ideal. Then, those who opt for a traditional marriage can determine
what this ritual means for them and can partake in a ceremony that validates
their union as one between husband and wife rather than ‘partners’ and
‘spouses’. Others can choose a form of marriage underpinned by their preferred
identities and moral norms. The separation of marriage from state has the merit
of allowing people with different moral outlooks to flourish in their chosen
way and not according to the dictates of officialdom.
No comments:
Post a Comment