A ruling idea of
the last two centuries has been materialism: the notion, as arch-materialist
Daniel Dennett asserts, that “there is only one sort of stuff, namely matter—the
physical stuff of physics, chemistry, and physiology—and the mind is somehow
nothing but a physical phenomenon.” One consequence of this belief has been the
rise of antihumanism—the stripping from people of their transcendent value and
a reduction of them to mere things in the world to be studied, understood, reshaped—and
ultimately controlled.
As Robert Zubrin shows in his valuable survey Merchants of Despair, antihumanism’s reductive view of human nature has underpinned movements like eugenics, population control, and radical environmentalism, all of which have been eager to sacrifice human life and well-being to achieve their dubious utopias. Zubrin, a Ph.D. in nuclear engineering and fellow of the Center for Security Policy, has previously authored popular books on energy and space exploration. He shows an engineer’s sharp eye for things as they are and a scientist’s respect for the limits of knowledge, especially as regards various pseudoscientific fads.
Zubrin begins with
Thomas Malthus, “the founding prophet of modern antihumanism,” who claimed in
his 1798 Essay on the Principle of Population that any
population always geometrically grows larger than the food supply. Malthus’s
argument ignored humans’ creative ingenuity, but his theories had catastrophic
consequences when applied to the real world. Believing that Ireland was
overpopulated, for example, the British government allowed this food-exporting
island to spiral downward into famine partly because, as Malthus himself urged,
“a great part of the population should be swept from the soil.” Over 1 million Irish
died of starvation and disease caused by malnutrition. Thirty years later, the
same policy of neglect contributed to a famine that killed as many as 10
million people in India, again because of the Malthusian fallacy that, as Sir
Evelyn Baring told Parliament, “every benevolent attempt made to mitigate the
effects of famine and defective sanitation serves but to enhance the evils
resulting from overpopulation.”
Charles Darwin embraced Malthus’s apocalyptic theories, too. Overpopulation, he believed, would eventually be cured by natural selection, the “weeding out of ‘unfit’ individuals and races.” As Darwin wrote in The Descent of Man: “At some future period . . . the civilized races of man will almost certainly exterminate, and replace, the savage races throughout the world.” Like Malthus, Darwin had no patience with sentimental Christian or Enlightenment ethics that sought to alleviate suffering and improve human life with medical advances such as vaccinations, or with asylums and other social-welfare institutions that cared for the sick, insane, or poor. Because of this effort “to check the process of elimination,” Darwin maintained, “the weak members of civilized societies propagate their kind. No one who has attended to the breeding of domestic animals will doubt that this must be highly injurious to the race of man.” As Zubrin summarizes Darwin’s argument: “Peace, plenty, care, and compassion were interferences in the course of nature. All progress was based on death.”
The mixture of
Malthusian and Darwinian theory soon conjured up racist eugenics. At the
forefront of the early eugenics movement was Darwin’s cousin, Francis Galton,
who also decried humanist sentimentalism. The “unfit” must be kept from
procreating, he argued, for “if these continued to procreate children, inferior
in moral, intellectual and physical qualities, it is easy to believe the time
may come when such persons would be considered as enemies to the State, and to
have forfeited all claims to kindness.” By the turn of the twentieth century,
these ideas had become articles of faith among many liberals and socialists.
Such cruel
pseudoscientific theories took a fatal turn in Germany, where eugenics found
its deadliest champion in biologist Ernst Haeckel, “an extreme racist, virulent
anti-Catholic bigot, anti-Semite, anti-Pole, pro-imperialist, Pan-German
fanatic” as well as a “militant atheist.” Haeckel and his followers sought to
replace Christian ethics with “Monism,” the aim of which was to further human
evolution through Germany’s conquest of inferior races and the elimination of
abnormal children and invalids. The ideas also took hold in America, championed
by men like General Francis Amasa Walker, president of M.I.T. In 1896, Walker
wrote in the Atlantic that Hungarian, Bohemian, Polish,
Italian, and Russian-Jewish immigrants were “beaten men from beaten races;
representing the worst failures in the struggle for existence,” possessing
“none of the ideas and aptitudes which fit men to take up readily and easily
the problem of self-care and self-government.” Theodore Roosevelt would later agree, expressing his
disdain for “the prevalent loose and sloppy talk about the general progress of
humanity, the equality and identity of races, and the like” as the product of
“well-meaning and feeble-minded sentimentalists.” These widespread prejudices,
buttressed by biased I.Q. tests, ultimately led in 1924 to the discriminatory
U.S. law that shut down immigration from countries considered inferior and
provided a pseudoscientific justification for race-based segregation.
The Holocaust
would discredit at least the public expression of eugenics. Zubrin shows that
the ideas lived on, though, repackaged as “population control” and concern for
the environment. Prewar eugenicists found a home in organizations like the
postwar Population Council, whose founding roster, Zubrin writes, “reads like a
eugenics movement reunion.” The same continuity exists between eugenics groups
and environmental organizations, such as the British Union for the Conservation
of Nature and the World Wildlife Fund. Particularly valuable is Zubrin’s
examination of the eugenic roots of Planned Parenthood, whose founder, Margaret
Sanger, wrote in 1919: “More children from the fit, less from the unfit—that is
the chief issue of birth control.” These movements, Zubrin writes, soon made up
“the imposing and influential population control establishment,” which became
entrenched at the United Nations and in U.S. government agencies. The efforts
of these groups were suspiciously concentrated in the developing world.
As Zubrin
meticulously documents, the obsession with overpopulation has led to attacks on
the economic and technological development that represents the best hope for
improving human life around the globe. The alliance of radical
environmentalism, population-control advocacy, and anticapitalist leftism
continues to prolong the misery of the Third World. Rachel Carson’s
scientifically challenged campaign against DDT led to the deaths of millions.
Paul Ehrlich’s spectacularly wrong Malthusian predictions helped legitimize
cruel policies, such as Lyndon Johnson’s withholding of food aid to India
during the 1966 famine. Ehrlich wanted food aid tied to sterilization and
birth-control programs and suggested adding “temporary sterilants to water
supplies or staple food,” with antidotes given only when the population reached
the desired size. He also wanted “luxury taxes” imposed on cribs, diapers, and
children’s toys. These neo-Malthusian theories ultimately led to the 1968
creation of the Club of Rome, whose influential study The Limits to
Growth shapes attitudes to the present day—for example, in the animus
against genetically modified foods. Now institutionalized in E.U. policy, the
refusal to allow genetically modified food denies vital crops (containing
nutrients and organic pesticides engineered into them) to the Third World.
The
anti-global-warming crusade against carbon-based energy is the latest assault
on progress and improvement. Zubrin is correct to call the climate-change
movement a “global antihuman cult.” Its assaults against dissent, embrace of
messianic leaders, and apocalyptic scenarios reveal a debased religious
sensibility rather than scientific rigor: “Right thinking will be rewarded,”
Zubrin writes of global-warming thought police like Al Gore and economist Paul
Krugman. “Wrong thinking will be punished. Many will be sacrificed. All will be
controlled. The gods will take back their fire.” The warmists’ growth-killing
programs, if implemented, would lead to mass immiseration.
As Zubrin
concludes, antihumanist ideas and programs represent a war against human
freedom and global solidarity: “If the world’s resources are fixed with only so
much to go around, then each new life is unwelcome, each unregulated act or
thought is a menace, every person is fundamentally the enemy of every other
person, and each race or nation is the enemy of every other race or nation. The
ultimate outcome of such a worldview can only be enforced stagnation, tyranny,
war, and genocide.” Contrary to the arguments of the “terrible simplifiers,” as
historian Jacob Burckhardt called those who reduce people to mere matter,
humans are capable of freedom, creativity, compassion, and love. We should
cherish these unique qualities rather than succumbing to antihumanism and
self-hatred.
No comments:
Post a Comment