The theory of class conflict
as a key to political history did not begin with Karl Marx. It began, as we
shall see further below, with two leading French libertarians inspired by J.B.
Say, Charles Comte (Say's son-in-law), and Charles Dunoyer, in the 1810s after
the restoration of the Bourbon monarchy. In contrast to the later Marxist
degeneration of class theory, the Comte-Dunoyer view held the inherent class
struggle to focus on which classes managed to gain
control of the state apparatus.
The ruling class is
whichever group has managed to seize state power; the ruled are those groups who are taxed and regulated
by those in command. Class interest, then, is defined as a group's relation to
the state. State rule, with its taxation and exercise of power, controls, and
conferring of subsidies and privileges, is the instrument that creates
conflicts between the rulers and the ruled. What we have, then, is a
"two-class" theory of class conflict, based on whether a group rules
or is ruled by the state. On the free market, on the other hand, there is no
class conflict, but a harmony of interest between all individuals in society
cooperating in and through production and exchange.
James Mill developed a similar theory in the 1820s and 1830s. It is not known whether he arrived at it independently or was influenced by the French libertarians; it is clear, however, that Mill's analysis was devoid of the rich applications to the history of western Europe that Comte, Dunoyer, and their young associate, the historian Augustin Thierry, had worked out. All government, Mill pointed out, was run by the ruling class, the few who dominated and exploited the ruled, the many.
Since all groups tend to act for their selfish interests, he noted, it is
absurd to expect the ruling clique to act altruistically for the "public
good." Like everyone else, they will use their opportunities for their own
gain, which means to loot the many, and to favor their own or allied special
interests as against those of the public. Hence Mill's habitual use of the term
"sinister" interests as against the good of the public. For Mill and
the radicals, we should note, the public good meant specifically laissez-faire
government confined to the minimal functions of police, defense and the
administration of justice.
Hence Mill, the preeminent
political theorist of the radicals, harked back to the libertarian
Commonwealthmen of the 18th century in stressing the need always to treat
government with suspicion and to provide checks to suppress state power. Mill
agreed with Bentham that "If not deterred, a ruling elite would be
predatory." The pursuit of sinister interests leads to endemic
"corruption" in politics, to sinecures, bureaucratic
"places" and subsidies. Mill lamented:
Think of the end [of
government] as it really is, in its own nature. Think next of the facility of
the means — justice, police, and security from foreign invaders. And then think
of the oppression practiced upon the people of England under the pretext of
providing them.
Never has libertarian ruling-class
theory been put more clearly or forcefully than in the words of Mill: there are
two classes, Mill declared, "the first class, those who plunder, are the
small number. They are the ruling Few. The second class, those who are
plundered, are the great number. They are the subject Many." Or, as
Professor Hamburger summed up Mill's position: "Politics was a struggle
between two classes — the avaricious rulers and their intended victims."
The great conundrum of
government, concluded Mill, was how to eliminate this plunder: to take away the
power "by which the class that plunder succeed in carrying on their
vocation, has ever been the great problem of government."
The "subject Many"
Mill accurately termed "the people," and it was probably Mill who
inaugurated the type of analysis that pits "the people" as a ruled
class in opposition to the "special interests." How, then, is the
power of the ruling class to be curbed? Mill thought he saw the answer:
The people must appoint
watchmen. Who are to watch the watchmen? The people themselves. There is no
other resource; and without this ultimate safeguard, the ruling Few will be
forever the scourge and oppression of the subject Many.
But how are the people themselves
to be the watchmen? To this ancient problem Mill provided what is by now a
standard answer in the Western world, but still not very satisfactory: by all
the people electing representatives to do the watching.
Unlike the French libertarian
analysts, James Mill was not interested in the history and development of state
power; he was interested only in the here and now. And in the here and now of
the England of his day, the ruling Few were the aristocracy, who ruled by means
of a highly limited suffrage and controlled "rotten boroughs" picking
representatives to Parliament. The English aristocracy was the ruling class;
the government of England, Mill charged, was "an aristocratical engine,
wielded by the aristocracy for their own benefit." Mill's son and ardent
disciple (at that time), John Stuart, argued in a Millian manner in debating
societies in London that England did not enjoy a
"mixed government," since a great majority of the House of Lords was
chosen by "200 families." These few aristocratic families
"therefore possess absolute control over the government … and if a
government controlled by 200 families is not an aristocracy, then such a thing
as an aristocracy cannot be said to exist." And since such a government is
controlled and run by a few, it is therefore "conducted wholly for the
benefit of a few."
It is this analysis that led
James Mill to place at the centre of his formidable political activity the
attainment of radical democracy, the universal suffrage of the people in
frequent elections by secret ballot. This was Mill's long-run goal, although he
was willing to settle temporarily — in what the Marxists would later call a
"transition demand" — for the Reform Bill of 1832, which greatly
widened the suffrage to the middle class. To Mill, the extension of democracy
was more important than laissez-faire, for to Mill the process of dethroning the aristocratic class was
more fundamental, since laissez-faire was one of the happy consequences
expected to flow from the replacement of aristocracy by the rule of all the
people. (In the modern American context, Mill's position would aptly be called
"right-wing populism.") Placing democracy as their central demand led
the Millian radicals in the 1840s to stumble and lose political significance by
refusing to ally themselves with the Anti-Corn Law League, despite their
agreement with its free trade and laissez-faire. For the Millians felt that
free trade was too much of a middle-class movement and detracted from an
overriding concentration on democratic reform.
Granted that the people would
displace aristocratic rule, did Mill have any reason for thinking that the
people would then exert their will on behalf of laissez-faire? Yes, and here
his reasoning was ingenious: while the ruling class had the fruits of their
exploitative rule in common, the people were a different kind of class: their
only interest in common was getting rid of the rule of special privilege. Apart
from that, the mass of the people have no common class interest that they could
ever actively pursue by means of the state. Furthermore, this interest in
eliminating special privilege is the common interest of all, and is therefore
the "public interest" as opposed to the special or sinister interests
of the few. The interest of the people coincides with universal interest and
with laissez-faire and liberty for all.
But how then explain that no
one can claim that the masses have always championed laissez-faire? — and that
the masses have all too often loyally supported the exploitative rule of the
few? Clearly, because the people, in this complex field of government and
public policy, have suffered from what the Marxists would later call
"false consciousness," an ignorance of where their interests truly
lie. It was then up to the intellectual vanguard, to Mill and his philosophic
radicals, to educate and organize the masses so that their consciousness would
become correct and they would then exert their irresistible strength to bring
about their own democratic rule and install laissez-faire. Even if we can
accept this general argument, the Millian radicals were unfortunately highly
overoptimistic about the time span for such consciousness-raising, and
political setbacks in the early 1840s led to their disillusionment in radical
politics and to the rapid disintegration of the radical movement. Curiously
enough, their leaders, such as John Stuart Mill and George and Harriet Grote,
while proclaiming their weary abandonment of political action or political
enthusiasm, in reality gravitated with astonishing rapidity toward the cozy
Whig centre that they had formerly scorned. Their proclaimed loss of interest
in politics was in reality a mask for loss of interest in radical politics.
No comments:
Post a Comment