F.A. Hayek
There can be no doubt that most of those in the
democracies who demand a central direction of all economic activity still
believe that socialism and individual freedom can be combined. Yet socialism
was early recognized by many thinkers as the gravest threat to freedom.
It
is rarely remembered now that socialism in its beginnings was frankly
authoritarian. It began quite openly as a reaction against the liberalism of
the French Revolution. The French writers who laid its foundation had no doubt
that their ideas could be put into practice only by a strong dictatorial
government. The first of modern planners, Saint-Simon, predicted that those who
did not obey his proposed planning boards would be "treated as
cattle."
Nobody
saw more clearly than the great political thinker de Tocqueville that democracy
stands in an irreconcilable conflict with socialism: "Democracy extends
the sphere of individual freedom," he said. "Democracy attaches all
possible value to each man," he said in 1848, "while socialism makes
each man a mere agent, a mere number. Democracy and socialism have nothing in
common but one word: equality. But notice the difference: while democracy seeks
equality in liberty, socialism seeks equality in restraint and servitude."
To allay these suspicions and to harness to its cart the strongest of all political motives—the craving for freedom — socialists began increasingly to make use of the promise of a "new freedom." Socialism was to bring "economic freedom," without which political freedom was "not worth having."
To
make this argument sound plausible, the word "freedom" was subjected
to a subtle change in meaning. The word had formerly meant freedom from
coercion, from the arbitrary power of other men. Now it was made to mean
freedom from necessity, release from the compulsion of the circumstances which
inevitably limit the range of choice of all of us. Freedom in this sense is, of
course, merely another name for power or wealth. The demand for the new freedom
was thus only another name for the old demand for a redistribution of wealth.
The
claim that a planned economy would produce a substantially larger output than
the competitive system is being progressively abandoned by most students of the
problem. Yet it is this false hope as much as anything which drives us along
the road to planning.
Although
our modern socialists' promise of greater freedom is genuine and sincere, in
recent years observer after observer has been impressed by the unforeseen
consequences of socialism, the extraordinary similarity in many respects of the
conditions under "communism" and "fascism." As the writer
Peter Drucker expressed it in 1939, "the complete collapse of the belief
in the attainability of freedom and equality through Marxism has forced Russia
to travel the same road toward a totalitarian society of un-freedom and
inequality which Germany has been following. Not that communism and fascism are
essentially the same. Fascism is the stage reached after communism has proved
an illusion, and it has proved as much an illusion in Russia as in pre-Hitler
Germany."
No
less significant is the intellectual outlook of the rank and file in the
communist and fascist movements in Germany before 1933. The relative ease with
which a young communist could be converted into a Nazi or vice versa was well
known, best of all to the propagandists of the two parties. The communists and
Nazis clashed more frequently with each other than with other parties simply
because they competed for the same type of mind and reserved for each other the
hatred of the heretic. Their practice showed how closely they are related. To
both, the real enemy, the man with whom they had nothing in common, was the
liberal of the old type. While to the Nazi the communist and to the communist
the Nazi, and to both the socialist, are potential recruits made of the right
timber, they both know that there can be no compromise between them and those
who really believe in individual freedom.
What
is promised to us as the Road to Freedom is in fact the Highroad to Servitude.
For it is not difficult to see what must be the consequences when democracy
embarks upon a course of planning. The goal of the planning will be described
by some such vague term as "the general welfare." There will be no
real agreement as to the ends to be attained, and the effect of the people's
agreeing that there must be central planning, without agreeing on the ends,
will be rather as if a group of people were to commit themselves to take a
journey together without agreeing where they want to go: with the result that
they may all have to make a journey which most of them do not want at all.
Democratic
assemblies cannot function as planning agencies. They cannot produce agreement
on everything — the whole direction of the resources of the nation-for the
number of possible courses of action will be legion. Even if a congress could,
by proceeding step by step and compromising at each point, agree on some
scheme, it would certainly in the end satisfy nobody.
To
draw up an economic plan in this fashion is even less possible than, for
instance, successfully to plan a military campaign by democratic procedure. As
in strategy it would become inevitable to delegate the task to experts. And
even if, by this expedient, a democracy should succeed in planning every sector
of economic activity, it would still have to face the problem of integrating
these separate plans into a unitary whole. There will be a stronger and
stronger demand that some board or some single individual should be given power
to act on their own responsibility. The cry for an economic dictator is a
characteristic stage in the movement toward planning. Thus the legislative body
will be reduced to choosing the persons who are to have practically absolute
power. The whole system will tend toward that kind of dictatorship in which the
head of the government is position by popular vote, but where he has all the
powers at his command to make certain that the vote will go in the direction he
desires.
Planning
leads to dictatorship because dictatorship is the most effective instrument of
coercion and, as such, essential if central planning on a large scale is to be
possible. There is no justification for the widespread belief that, so long as
power is conferred by democratic procedure, it cannot be arbitrary; it is not
the source of power which prevents it from being arbitrary; to be free from
dictatorial qualities, the power must also be limited. A true
"dictatorship of the proletariat," even if democratic in form, if it
undertook centrally to direct the economic system, would probably destroy
personal freedom as completely as any autocracy has ever done.
Individual
freedom cannot be reconciled with the supremacy of one single purpose to which
the whole of society is permanently subordinated. To a limited extent we
ourselves experience this fact in wartime, when subordination of almost
everything to the immediate and pressing need is the price at which we preserve
our freedom in the long run. The fashionable phrases about doing for the
purposes of peace what we have learned.to do for the purposes of war are
completely misleading, for it is sensible temporarily to sacrifice freedom in
order to make it more secure in the future, but it is quite a different thing
to sacrifice liberty permanently in the interests of a planned economy.
To
those who have watched the transition from socialism to fascism at close
quarters, the connection between the two systems is obvious. The realization of
the socialist program means the destruction of freedom. Democratic socialism,
the great utopia of the last few generations, is simply not achievable.
No comments:
Post a Comment