A
feeling of moral superiority is often compensation for the lack of any other
kind of superiority, and has the advantage that it can never be decisively
disproved. With respect to capital punishment, Europeans feel morally superior
to Americans because they have abolished it as a relic of judicial barbarism.
So complete has been the revolution in moral sensibility that they speak as if
the French foreswore the guillotine before the Roman invasion rather than in
1981, against the majority opinion of the public.
The question of capital punishment has
long agitated the minds of intellectuals, and recently I had the good fortune
to find and buy The Punishment of Death by Henry Romilly, published in 1886, an
anti-capital punishment tract. Romilly was the son of the lawyer and
politician, Sir Samuel Romilly, one of the early abolitionists; Henry is
therefore a case of hereditary abolitionism. He is not, of course, to be
despised on that account.
Some of his arguments seem distinctly odd. For example, he says that the frequent reports of the repentance of the murderer on the scaffold, and of his dignified conduct thereon, create a sympathy for him that would tend to lessen the public abhorrence of his crime and therefore decrease the general inhibitions against committing like crimes. This is distinctly far-fetched.
Romilly denies that the death penalty is
a deterrent to murder because, at the moment of killing, the murderer is
usually in such a state of passion that nothing can enter his mind to prevent
him from committing the act. He does not say to himself ‘I might swing for
this,’ and desist; he realizes it, usually to his chagrin, only after the
event.
Recently, I stumbled across evidence
that showed that this was wrong, that the death penalty probably does deter
murder. I had read a book called Murder Followed by Suicide,
by the distinguished doctor and criminologist, D J West, which was published in
1965, the very year of the abolition of the death penalty in Britain.
For several decades before the date of
publication, a third of all homicides in the country had been followed by the
suicide of the perpetrator. In the great majority of these cases, the
perpetrator was mad, and actually would not have been found guilty (because of
his or her insanity) had he or she lived to face trial. The title of the book,
then, while dramatic, was slightly inaccurate. It should have been Homicide Followed by Suicide,
but that does not have quite the same ring to it.
The suicide who had just killed was
likely to be suffering from delusions, for example that by killing his wife and
children he was sparing them something far worse at the hands of the
conspirators who were persecuting him. While most killers are men, a much
higher proportion of mad killers were women.
It occurred to me that nothing on earth
would deter these mad killers from their course of action: they were like
Romilly’s killers in the grip of an ungovernable passion. So the death penalty
would not deter them; but if, I
hypothesized, it exerted a deterrent effect upon other potential killers, what
one would see after the abolition of the death penalty was a rise in the total
number of homicides, but a reduction in the proportion of them followed by
suicide.
And this is precisely what happened.
Thanks to researches by my friend, the criminologist David Fraser, I learnt
that, while the general homicide rate increased after 1965, the proportion of
homicides followed by suicide fell, from a third – stable for many years before
the abolition – to about one fourteenth. Moreover, the absolute number of
homicides followed by suicide, while showing a tendency to fall (perhaps
because of the earlier and more effective treatment of the psychotic), remained
rather similar
At the very least, these facts were
compatible with the deterrent effect of capital punishment. No doubt other
interpretations of them were possible, but the most natural interpretation
seemed to be that the possibility of being hanged – never more than a possibility,
since no more than an eighth of murderers were ever executed – concentrated the
minds of the violent
Does this, then, settle the question of
capital punishment? The answer is obviously ‘No.’ The effectiveness of a
punishment is not sufficient to justify it. We are horrified by the amputation
of thieves’ hands not because it is ineffective, or even because it is unjust,
but because it is barbaric. The relationship between facts and policy is more
complex than is sometimes believed.
It seems to me that the decisive
argument against the death penalty is that, even in the most scrupulous
jurisdictions, mistakes are made: and for the state to put to death an innocent
man is a terrible thing, one that is likely in the end to undermine its
legitimacy in the eyes of many. A supporter of the death penalty to whom I put
this point retorted immediately that it was easy to refute it, because it could
be shown that murderers repeated their murders more often than the wrong man
was executed, therefore the balance was in favor of the death penalty. I
replied that this seemed to me more a refutation of utilitarianism than an
argument in favor of the death penalty, but as with most such discussions, no
final agreement was reached between us.
As with so many questions, those on one
side are more at pains to refute the arguments of those on the other than to
find the truth. This is partly for reasons of vanity, as Schopenhauer would no
doubt say; but there is something else besides. We find it difficult and
disturbing to hold in our minds arguments of the form ‘On the one hand, on the
other.’ If we are for capital punishment we want it to be good in all respects,
with no serious drawbacks; if we are against it, we want it to be bad in all
respects, with no serious advantages. We want the world of facts to dictate to
us, virtually, how to act; but this it will never do. We always have to make a choice.
No comments:
Post a Comment