by Tibor Machan
ln October 1986 Professor James M.
Buchanan was awarded the Nobel Prize for economics. He received the award for
his pioneering work in public choice theory, a branch of economic analysis that
studies the behavior of politicians and bureaucrats, especially in a
representative democracy such as the United States.
Professor
Buchanan, who now teaches at George Mason University in Fairfax, Virginia,
developed his theory in cooperation with several other economists, most notably
Professor Gordon Tullock. (During the development of public choice theory both
of these economists taught at the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State
University, Blacksburg, Virginia.) Their book, The Calculus of Consent (University
of Michigan Press, 1962), pioneered this new application of economics. Since
its publication, other books and journals have followed, including the
scholarly journal of the Center for Study of Public Choice, Public Choice, which published extensive and complex studies
on a great variety of topics of concern to public choice theorists. Professors
Buchanan and Tullock also have inspired numerous other economists,
philosophers, political scientists and legal theorists to explore various
implications of the public choice approach.
What do public choice theorists claim? Essentially they hold that when people enter government and become "public" servants, they act on the same motives they would if they were agents in the marketplace. "Public" servants are motivated no less by private interests than are men and women in business. As Buchanan puts it, "Politicians and bureaucrats are seen as ordinary persons, and 'politics' is viewed as a set of arrangements, a game if you will, in which many players with quite disparate objectives interact so as to generate a set of outcomes that may not be either internally consistent or efficient."1
Public choice theory also implies, in Buchanan's words, that "The bureaucracy can play off one set of constituents against others, ensuring that budgets rise much beyond plausibly efficient limits."2
To appreciate
adequately why public choice theory delivers its paradoxical conclusions
concerning what our public servants actually do—namely, further their own
private or vested interests—one needs to know the basic postulates of
contemporary economic science. Mainstream economics today assumes that we
always behave so as to maximize our satisfactions or wealth. As another Nobel
winner in economics, Milton Friedman, put it,
"... every individual serves his own private interest. ... The great Saints of history have served their 'private interest' just as the most money-grubbing miser has served his interest. The private interest is whatever it is that drives an individual."3
Or as another
influential economist, Professor Gary Becker put it as he spelled out the
fundamental tenets of his social-scientific approach to understanding human
affairs, "The combined assumptions of maximizing behavior, market equilibrium,
and stable preferences, used relentlessly and unflinchingly, form the heart of
the economic approach as I see it."4
What this
view means in common parlance is that economic science assumes that we are all
driven by our desires. These are ranked in order so that some of us prefer
sweet things, fresh air, excitement, music, sports, in that order; others
don't. It is such desires to have or do various things that motivate us and
there is nothing from the economic point of view that needs to be said about
whether these are good things or bad. And in the more extreme scientistic
versions of economics, there is nothing anyone can do about what will motivate
people. Our motives are simply what explains what we do, period. And if we wish
to understand people's behavior, we need to pay attention to the fact that they
are motivated by their desires.
Of course,
there are various nuances in economic theory which are not captured in the
above general statements. But the main point is that we must do what we desire
to do. And public choice theorists take this view into the special area of
understanding the behavior of public officials by asserting, as a corollary of
general economic analysis, that not only do we do this as shoppers, bankers,
merchants, corporate executives, brokers and the like, but also as
"public" servants.
Revising
Common Sense
There would
be little interest in public choice analysis if it did not serve to modify our
non- technical understanding of how public servants behave. That is why
Professor Buchanan was honored with the Nobel Prize. He points out something
that we normally were not aware of—indeed, something that we very likely would
have missed without him.
Ordinarily we
take it that politicians, bureaucrats, diplomats and other "public"
servants are devoted to the public interest, not to what they privately desire.
At least, we take this as their professional responsibility, something they
ought to be doing, at least when they carry on in good faith. A public servant
is not supposed to be a profit maximizer, one who wants to satisfy himself in a
competitive marketplace. Put plainly, such as person is supposed to pursue the
public interest.
Yet public
choice theorists deny this common assumption. What they say by way of economic
analysis may be put in more familiar terms: They believe that people in public
positions really try to advance their own lot before anyone else's. But is this
the whole story?
Public
versus Private Service in the Welfare State
Governments
of welfare states get involved in all sorts of activities to pursue particular
goals that various individuals and groups of citizens seek to achieve. They
further the lot of artists (via the various arts councils and endowments),
farmers (via subsidies and price support programs), various professions (via
licensing requirements), auto workers or high-tech industries (via trade
policies) and so on. The welfare state expects a great deal of its government
and even if officials conscientiously tried to fulfill their duties to their
constituencies, they would go astray in their assigned tasks. It is not
surprising, furthermore, that "public servants" who serve special
interests are not able to keep their minds on what the public interest happens
to be.
Virtually no
meaningful distinction between the public and the private interest is possible
when government promotes the same ends that are pursued in the private sector.
Indeed, as soon as some people are dissatisfied with how the private sector
achieves some private purpose, governments are quickly approached to promote
that same purpose. Too many examples come to mind to pick the most appropriate
one, but a very apt recent case is day care centers. Although hundreds of
private companies and other agencies fulfill the task of serving single or
working parents with child care facilities, there is constant support from
various segments of the public for government to expand its involvement in this
activity. From AIDS research to trade restrictions, the bulk of contemporary
legislation comes to little more than government helping people with their
private or vested interests, misnaming it all as the pursuit of the public
interest. There appears to be no public interest distinct from the varied
private or special interests the government now serves.
Here is a
case that is familiar to me. The federal government recently started the Jacob
J. Javits National Graduate Fellowship Program (NGFP). People from various
branches of the educational establishment were appointed to a board of
overseers. Colleges and various groups devoted to undergraduate education
beseech the board to conduct an effective program, one that really helps
deserving undergraduates. At the same time, of course, other people are asking
the government to work toward other goals.
In this
example the public choice theorist would find a clear application of the
assumptions of his view. Indeed, this is one way of describing what happens in
cases such as the above that conforms to what public choice theory would
predict: To wit, those on the overseeing board eagerly promote the efficient
administration and ample funding of the program in question. They select the
appropriate panels and panel chiefs, they encourage the supporting staff, in
this case from the Department of Education, and they report back to Congress
with requests of further and more abundant support for the program.
Vested
versus Public Interest: A Meaningful Contrast
But there is
another way to describe what is going on here, a way that may be compatible
with public choice theory yet does not cast the situation in the same
conceptual light. And it may be important to try to do this because the public
choice theory idea is rather pessimistic—if we really are all just trying to
gain our own advantage, even when we swear that that is not what we will be
doing in our role as politicians or bureaucrats, what's the use of even
pointing this out? Those assigned to fix the situation, even at the
institutional level (as Buchanan suggests), would be simply carrying on in the
same hopeless way as have all the other "public" servants.
In a case
such as the NGFP, the appointed overseers and administrators are asked to do a
good job. And they are asked to report to Congress about how well they are
managing to do what members of Congress have decided on doing. And in most of
these cases these people see that the money they have to administer is not
enough to do the job as well as they can conceive of doing it. After all, if
the program is to be carried out, it should be done right, shouldn't it?
As described
above, this does not seem to be a case of politicians and bureaucrats simply
wishing to fulfill their desires, nor of being driven by private interest. Not
quite, although that is clearly part of it, especially when we focus on the
staff hired to administer the programs in question, that is, "those
persons," as Buchanan describes them, "who actually supply the goods
and services that are provided via governmental auspices."
Modifying
Public Choice Theory
Some friendly
critics now make a point against public choice theory that seems to take into
account the above understanding of what goes on in public administration. They
seem to be aware that referring merely to the private or vested interest of
those involved in carrying out the project fails to give full justice to the
situation. They contend that in order for public choice theory to be an
adequate explanation of how politicians and bureaucrats behave one must also
consider the belief system that motivates them − e.g., whether they are conservatives, liberals, libertarians, socialists, whatnots, and whether they have
a bona fide commitment to the programs involved or are merely advancing their
private roles in the administration of such a program. They may even have a
bona fide public service orientation, albeit somewhat unorthodox in what this
means.
Professors
Joseph P. Kalt and Mark Zupan, of Harvard's Kennedy School of Government and
the University of Southern California, respectively, have argued that an
"ideology" variable must be added to the public choice or
"economic man" model so as to explain what members of the U.S.
Congress and other bureaucrats do as they approach their various projects. In
particular, they studied what the United States Senate did in the case of coal
strip mining. Their statistical analysis shows that the "ideology" variable
explains the voting patterns of the Senate on the Surface Mining Control and
Reclamation Act (passed in 1977) better than does the public choice model. In
short, in addition to considering the desires of the legislators to be
re-elected, the bureaucrats to continue on and expand their jobs, etc., we need
also consider the broader political ideals of public agents.
Some people,
of course, will suggest that adding the ideological variable does no damage to
the economic man model. They will say that the urge to follow an ideology is no
less a case of utility maximization than the urge to seek a vacation in the
Bahamas or to increase one's income. But this simply makes shambles of the
explanatory value of the economic man model. Any factor or model that explains anything
whatever − e.g., self-defeating as well as self-serving conduct − simply
explains nothing much! If economic man explains the bank robber as well as the
banker, what can we learn from the explanation? In no science would this kind
of approach be admitted.
In order to
avoid this vacuousness, the ideological variable has to be seen as adding a
dimension-namely, what kind of conduct human beings take to be proper, what
they see as binding on them quite apart from what they may prefer. This is how
we can make sense of self- control, restraint, integrity, etc., not by lumping
them all together and thereby wiping the human world clean of meaningful
distinctions.
Indeed,
Professor Buchanan himself has focused his attention on some of the broader
philosophical issues concerning public choice, finding the pure economic
explanation of human behavior insufficient. The following passage from Buchanan
will shed light on just how his thinking differs from the pure economic man
approach to understanding political behavior:
. . . once the body politic begins to get overly concerned about the distribution of the pie under existing property-rights assignments and legal rules, once we begin to think either about the personal gains from law-breaking, privately or publicly, or about the disparities between existing imputations and those estimated to be forthcoming under some idealized anarchy, we are necessarily precluding and forestalling the achievement of potential structural changes that might increase the size of the pie for all. Too much concern for [distributive] "justice" acts to insure that "growth" will not take place, and for reasons much more basic than the familiar economic incentives arguments.5
In other
words, focusing on the behavior of public servants within the current political
and legal framework is not sufficient for understanding what alternatives face
us in understanding and conducting public affairs. It can serve to block basic
reform which is itself not impossible despite the motivations of public
servants.
Ideas
Can Have Consequences
Basic reform
may emerge as part of the ideology that public servants themselves can infuse
into their conduct in the public realm. If public servants were to become
convinced that the promotion of some popular project is indeed not a proper government activity in the first place, then despite what
they might do in circumstances which are not governed by this "ideological"
consideration, they could come to behave very differently from what public
choice theory predicts.
In
particular, suppose that a politician or bureaucrat came to understand that as
the government is conceived under the welfare state, its operations must
produce the famous tragedy of the commons − the overuse of the
public realm (which in this case is public funds). This is a genuine tragedy in
that something is morally amiss, yet given some of the structural features of
government, it is not possible to remedy matters. Indeed, the problem of
balancing the budget versus promoting worthwhile goals is just the sort that
characterizes this tragedy − everyone conscientiously aims to serve worthwhile
goals, yet in the process a general shortage of the means to support such goals
is created throughout the community.
Once this is
understood by public servants, it could turn out that they will discipline
themselves to focus on the appropriate reforms. There are in our time ample
cases of such realignment of public behavior. Despite the fact, for example,
that the Javits Program serves a valuable purpose that no one can fault, there
are those involved in it who regard it as not the proper function of government
to serve this purpose. This idea may be unusual these days and indeed such
people are sharply resisted by many of their colleagues and those who come to
"testify" before board meetings of the administrators of the program − i.e.,
supporters and lobbyists. Pleas about how similar projects, aimed at helping
the sciences, are receiving so much more funding, so why not carry forth with
this little bit for the humanities are often met with: "This is where I
can do public service and if I had the chance to do it elsewhere, I
would."
The
realignment may, of course, come from a different understanding of public
affairs, so the particular "ideology" that may lead to the reform
must be carefully scrutinized, apart from the analysis of public conduct
itself. But clearly the "ideology" of the public servant, not simply
his or her vested interests, has a bearing on the development of public
affairs. The reason this is obscured and why public choice theory is only now
adjusting itself to the insight is that the welfare state is structurally
incapable of facilitating the serving of a distinct public interest when it
implies by its scope that no distinction between public and private concerns
exists. This (socialist) notion can cause much confusion.
Conclusion
There is
reason to think that while economic analysis is crucial for understanding
virtually any area of human behavior, it is not sufficient for such an
understanding. There are, for example, politicians who buck trends, who see
that the fulfillment of their responsibilities lies with remedying, as best as
possible, the consequences of the special interest hustling that dominates the
politics of the welfare state. Some of these support − incidentally,
with the advice of Professor Buchanan − the Balanced Budget Amendment
movement. Others support appointments to various government bodies knowing that
those whom they will appoint are not going to ask for more support for these
programs. They will, instead, urge greater and greater restraint so as to solve
the broader problem of creeping statism, holding that the special problem the
program had been established to solve should be handled by people outside the
scope of politics.
Professor
Buchanan taught us that when government extends beyond its proper scope, it is
very hard to limit its expansion. Yet we can still rely on the convictions of a
few brave public servants who will try to resist the advances of statism and on
the James Buchanans of the world to tell us that government must be limited to
genuine public service—the maintenance and preservation of justice as spelled
out in the Declaration of Independence.
NOTES
1 James Buchanan, "Why Governments
'Got Out of Hand,'" New York Times,
October 26, 1986.
2 Ibid.
3 Milton Friedman, "The Line We Dare Not Cross," Encounter, November 1976.
4Gary S. Becker, The Economic Approach to Human Behavior (University of Chicago Press, 1976), p. 5.
5James Buchanan, "Boundaries on Social Contract," Reason Papers, No. 2, 1975, p. 27 (my emphasis in last sentence).
2 Ibid.
3 Milton Friedman, "The Line We Dare Not Cross," Encounter, November 1976.
4Gary S. Becker, The Economic Approach to Human Behavior (University of Chicago Press, 1976), p. 5.
5James Buchanan, "Boundaries on Social Contract," Reason Papers, No. 2, 1975, p. 27 (my emphasis in last sentence).
No comments:
Post a Comment