by Murray N. Rothbard
In the spring of 1981, conservative Republicans in the
House of Representatives cried. They cried because, in the first flush of the
Reagan Revolution that was supposed to bring drastic cuts in taxes and government
spending, as well as a balanced budget, they were being asked by the White
House and their own leadership to vote for an increase in the statutory limit
on the federal public debt, which was then scraping the legal ceiling of $1
trillion. They cried because all of their lives they had voted against an
increase in public debt, and now they were being asked, by their own party and
their own movement, to violate their lifelong principles. The White House and
its leadership assured them that this breach in principle would be their last:
that it was necessary for one last increase in the debt limit to give President
Reagan a chance to bring about a balanced budget and to begin to reduce the
debt. Many of these Republicans tearfully announced that they were taking this
fateful step because they deeply trusted their president, who would not let
them down.
Famous last words. In a sense, the Reagan handlers
were right: there were no more tears, no more complaints, because the
principles themselves were quickly forgotten, swept into the dustbin of
history. Deficits and the public debt have piled up mountainously since then,
and few people care, least of all conservative Republicans. Every few years,
the legal limit is raised automatically. By the end of the Reagan reign the
federal debt was $2.6 trillion; now it is $3.5 trillion and rising rapidly. And
this is the rosy side of the picture, because if you add in
"off-budget" loan guarantees and contingencies, the grand total
federal debt is $20 trillion.
Before the Reagan era, conservatives were clear about how they felt about deficits and the public debt: a balanced budget was good, and deficits and the public debt were bad, piled up by free-spending Keynesians and socialists, who absurdly proclaimed that there was nothing wrong or onerous about the public debt. In the famous words of the left-Keynesian apostle of "functional finance," Professor Abba Lernr, there is nothing wrong with the public debt because "we owe it to ourselves." In those days, at least, conservatives were astute enough to realize that it made an enormous amount of difference whether — slicing through the obfuscatory collective nouns — one is a member of the "we" (the burdened taxpayer) or of the "ourselves" (those living off the proceeds of taxation).
Since Reagan, however, intellectual-political life has
gone topsy-turvy. Conservatives and allegedly "free-market"
economists have turned handsprings trying to find new reasons why
"deficits don't matter," why we should all relax and enjoy the
process. Perhaps the most absurd argument of Reaganomists was that we should
not worry about growing public debt because it is being matched on the federal
balance sheet by an expansion of public "assets." Here was a new
twist on free-market macroeconomics: things are going well because the value of
government assets is rising! In that case, why not have the government
nationalize all assets outright? Reaganomists, indeed, came up with every
conceivable argument for the public debt except the phrase of Abba Lerner, and
I am convinced that they did not recycle that phrase because it would be
difficult to sustain with a straight face at a time when foreign ownership of
the national debt is skyrocketing. Even apart from foreign ownership, it is far
more difficult to sustain the Lerner thesis than before; in the late 1930s,
when Lerner enunciated his thesis, total federal interest payments on the
public debt were $1 billion; now they have zoomed to $200 billion, the
third-largest item in the federal budget, after the military and Social
Security: the "we" are looking ever shabbier compared to the
"ourselves."
To think sensibly about the public debt, we first have
to go back to first principles and consider debt in general. Put simply, a
credit transaction occurs when C, the creditor, transfers a sum of money (say
$1,000) to D, the debtor, in exchange for a promise that D will repay C in a
year's time the principal plus interest. If the agreed interest rate on the
transaction is 10 percent, then the debtor obligates himself to pay in a year's
time $1,100 to the creditor. This repayment completes the transaction, which in
contrast to a regular sale, takes place over time.
So far, it is clear that there is nothing
"wrong" with private debt. As with any private trade or exchange on
the market, both parties to the exchange benefit, and no one loses. But suppose
that the debtor is foolish, gets himself in over his head, and then finds that
he can't repay the sum he had agreed on? This, of course is a risk incurred by debt,
and the debtor had better keep his debts down to what he can surely repay. But
this is not a problem of debt alone. Any consumer may spend foolishly; a man
may blow his entire paycheck on an expensive trinket and then find that he
can't feed his family. So consumer foolishness is hardly a problem confined to
debt alone. But there is one crucial difference: if a man gets in over his head
and he can't pay, the creditor suffers too, because the debtor has failed to
return the creditor's property. In a profound sense, the debtor who fails to
repay the $1,100 owed to the creditor has stolen property that belongs to the
creditor; we have here not simply a civil debt, but a tort, an aggression
against another's property.
In earlier centuries, the insolvent debtor's offense
was considered grave, and unless the creditor was willing to
"forgive" the debt out of charity, the debtor continued to owe the
money plus accumulating interest, plus penalty for continuing nonpayment.
Often, debtors were clapped into jail until they could pay — a bit draconian
perhaps, but at least in the proper spirit of enforcing property rights and
defending the sanctity of contracts. The major practical problem was the
difficulty for debtors in prison to earn the money to repay the loan; perhaps
it would have been better to allow the debtor to be free, provided that his
continuing income went to paying the creditor his just due.
As early as the 17th century, however, governments
began sobbing about the plight of the unfortunate debtors, ignoring the fact
that the insolvent debtors had gotten themselves into their own fix, and they
began to subvert their own proclaimed function of enforcing contracts.
Bankruptcy laws were passed which, increasingly, let the debtors off the hook
and prevented the creditors from obtaining their own property. Theft was
increasingly condoned, improvidence was subsidized, and thrift was hobbled. In
fact, with the modern device of Chapter 11, instituted by the Bankruptcy Reform
Act of 1978, inefficient and improvident managers and stockholders are not only
let off the hook, but they often remain in positions of power, debt-free and
still running their firms, and plaguing consumers and creditors with their
inefficiencies. Modern utilitarian neoclassical economists see nothing wrong
with any of this; the market, after all, "adjusts" to these changes
in the law. It is true that the market can adjust to almost anything, but so
what? Hobbling creditors means that interest rates rise permanently, to the
sober and honest as well as the improvident; but why should the former be taxed
to subsidize the latter? But there are deeper problems with this utilitarian
attitude. It is the same amoral claim, from the same economists, that there is
nothing wrong with rising crime against residents or storekeepers of the inner
cities. The market, they assert, will adjust and discount for such high crime
rates, and therefore rents and housing values will be lower in the inner-city
areas. So everything will be taken care of. But what sort of consolation is
that? And what sort of justification for aggression and crime?
In a just society, then, only voluntary forgiveness by
creditors would let debtors off the hook; otherwise, bankruptcy laws are an
unjust invasion of the property rights of creditors.
One myth about "debtors'" relief is that
debtors are habitually poor and creditors rich, so that intervening to save
debtors is merely a requirement of egalitarian "fairness." But this
assumption was never true: in business, the wealthier the businessman the more
likely he is to be a large debtor. It is the Donald Trumps and Robert Maxwells
of this world whose debts spectacularly exceed their assets. Intervention on
behalf of debtors has generally been lobbied for by large businesses with large
debts. In modern corporations, the effect of ever-tightening bankruptcy laws
has been to hobble the creditor-bondholders for the benefit of the stockholders
and the existing managers, who are usually installed by, and allied with, a few
dominant large stockholders. The very fact that a corporation is insolvent
demonstrates that its managers have been inefficient, and they should be
removed promptly from the scene. Bankruptcy laws that keep prolonging the rule
of existing managers, then, not only invade the property rights of the
creditors; they also injure the consumers and the entire economic system by
preventing the market from purging the inefficient and improvident managers and
stockholders and from shifting the ownership of industrial assets to the more efficient
creditors. Not only that; in a recent law review article, Bradley and
Rosenzweig have shown that the stockholders, too, as well as the creditors,
have lost a significant amount of assets due to the installation of Chapter 11
in 1978. As they write, "if bondholders and stockholders are both losers
under Chapter 11, then who are the winners?" The winners, remarkably but
unsurprisingly, turn out to be the existing, inefficient corporate managers, as
well as the assorted lawyers, accountants, and financial advisers who earn huge
fees from bankruptcy reorganizations.
In a free-market economy that respects property
rights, the volume of private debt is self-policed by the necessity to repay
the creditor, since no Papa Government is letting you off the hook. In
addition, the interest rate a debtor must pay depends not only on the general
rate of time preference but on the degree of risk he as a debtor poses to the
creditor. A good credit risk will be a "prime borrower," who will pay
relatively low interest; on the other hand, an improvident person or a
transient who has been bankrupt before, will have to pay a much higher interest
rate, commensurate with the degree of risk on the loan.
Most people, unfortunately, apply the same analysis to
public debt as they do to private. If sanctity of contracts should rule in the
world of private debt, shouldn't they be equally as sacrosanct in public debt?
Shouldn't public debt be governed by the same principles as private? The answer
is no, even though such an answer may shock the sensibilities of most people.
The reason is that the two forms of debt-transaction are totally different. If
I borrow money from a mortgage bank, I have made a contract to transfer my
money to a creditor at a future date; in a deep sense, he is the true owner of
the money at that point, and if I don't pay I am robbing him of his just
property. But when government borrows money, it does not pledge its own money;
its own resources are not liable. Government commits not its own life, fortune,
and sacred honor to repay the debt, but ours. This is a horse, and a
transaction, of a very different color.
For unlike the rest of us, government sells no
productive good or service and therefore earns nothing. It can only get money
by looting our resources through taxes, or through the hidden tax of legalized
counterfeiting known as "inflation." There are some exceptions, of
course, such as when the government sells stamps to collectors or carries our
mail with gross inefficiency, but the overwhelming bulk of government revenues
is acquired through taxation or its monetary equivalent. Actually, in the days
of monarchy, and especially in the medieval period before the rise of the
modern state, kings got the bulk of their income from their private estates —
such as forests and agricultural lands. Their debt, in other words, was more
private than public, and as a result, their debt amounted to next to nothing
compared to the public debt that began with a flourish in the late 17th
century.
The public debt transaction, then, is very different
from private debt. Instead of a low-time-preference creditor exchanging money
for an IOU from a high-time-preference debtor, the government now receives
money from creditors, both parties realizing that the money will be paid back not
out of the pockets or the hides of the politicians and bureaucrats, but out of
the looted wallets and purses of the hapless taxpayers, the subjects of the
state. The government gets the money by tax-coercion; and the public creditors,
far from being innocents, know full well that their proceeds will come out of
that selfsame coercion. In short, public creditors are willing to hand over
money to the government now in order to receive a share of tax loot in the
future. This is the opposite of a free market, or a genuinely voluntary
transaction. Both parties are immorally contracting to participate in the
violation of the property rights of citizens in the future. Both parties,
therefore, are making agreements about other people's property, and both deserve
the back of our hand. The public credit transaction is not a genuine contract
that need be considered sacrosanct, any more than robbers parceling out their
shares of loot in advance should be treated as some sort of sanctified
contract.
Any melding of public debt into a private transaction
must rest on the common but absurd notion that taxation is really
"voluntary," and that whenever the government does anything,
"we" are willingly doing it. This convenient myth was wittily and
trenchantly disposed of by the great economist Joseph Schumpeter: "The
theory which construes taxes on the analogy of club dues or of the purchases
of, say, a doctor only proves how far removed this part of the social sciences
is from scientific habits of mind." Morality and economic utility
generally go hand in hand. Contrary to Alexander Hamilton, who spoke for a
small but powerful clique of New York and Philadelphia public creditors, the
national debt is not a "national blessing." The annual government
deficit, plus the annual interest payment that keeps rising as the total debt
accumulates, increasingly channels scarce and precious private savings into
wasteful government boondoggles, which "crowd out" productive
investments. Establishment economists, including Reaganomists, cleverly fudge
the issue by arbitrarily labeling virtually all government spending as
"investments," making it sound as if everything is fine and dandy
because savings are being productively "invested." In reality,
however, government spending only qualifies as "investment" in an
Orwellian sense; government actually spends on behalf of the "consumer
goods" and desires of bureaucrats, politicians, and their dependent client
groups. Government spending, therefore, rather than being "investment,"
is consumer spending of a peculiarly wasteful and unproductive sort, since it
is indulged not by producers but by a parasitic class that is living off, and
increasingly weakening, the productive private sector. Thus, we see that
statistics are not in the least "scientific" or
"value-free"; how data are classified — whether, for example,
government spending is "consumption" or "investment" —
depends upon the political philosophy and insights of the classifier.
Deficits and a mounting debt, therefore, are a growing
and intolerable burden on the society and economy, both because they raise the
tax burden and increasingly drain resources from the productive to the
parasitic, counterproductive, "public" sector. Moreover, whenever
deficits are financed by expanding bank credit — in other words, by creating
new money — matters become still worse, since credit inflation creates
permanent and rising price inflation as well as waves of boom-bust
"business cycles."
It is for all these reasons that the Jeffersonians and
Jacksonians (who, contrary to the myths of historians, were extraordinarily
knowledgeable in economic and monetary theory) hated and reviled the public
debt. Indeed, the national debt was paid off twice in American history, the
first time by Thomas Jefferson and the second, and undoubtedly the last time,
by Andrew Jackson.
Unfortunately, paying off a national debt that will
soon reach $4 trillion would quickly bankrupt the entire country. Think about
the consequences of imposing new taxes of $4 trillion in the United States next
year! Another way, and almost as devastating, a way to pay off the public debt
would be to print $4 trillion of new money — either in paper dollars or by
creating new bank credit. This method would be extraordinarily inflationary,
and prices would quickly skyrocket, ruining all groups whose earnings did not
increase to the same extent, and destroying the value of the dollar. But in
essence this is what happens in countries that hyper-inflate, as Germany did in
1923, and in countless countries since, particularly the Third World. If a
country inflates the currency to pay off its debt, prices will rise so that the
dollars or marks or pesos the creditor receives are worth a lot less than the
dollars or pesos they originally lent out. When an American purchased a 10,000
mark German bond in 1914, it was worth several thousand dollars; those 10,000
marks by late 1923 would not have been worth more than a stick of bubble gum.
Inflation, then, is an underhanded and terribly destructive way of indirectly
repudiating the "public debt"; destructive because it ruins the
currency unit, which individuals and businesses depend upon for calculating all
their economic decisions.
I propose, then, a seemingly drastic but actually far
less destructive way of paying off the public debt at a single blow: outright
debt repudiation. Consider this question: why should the poor, battered
citizens of Russia or Poland or the other ex-Communist countries be bound by
the debts contracted by their former Communist masters? In the Communist
situation, the injustice is clear: that citizens struggling for freedom and for
a free-market economy should be taxed to pay for debts contracted by the
monstrous former ruling class. But this injustice only differs by degree from
"normal" public debt. For, conversely, why should the Communist
government of the Soviet Union have been bound by debts contracted by the
Czarist government they hated and overthrew? And why should we, struggling
American citizens of today, be bound by debts created by a past ruling elite
who contracted these debts at our expense? One of the cogent arguments against
paying blacks "reparations" for past slavery is that we, the living,
were not slaveholders. Similarly, we the living did not contract for either the
past or the present debts incurred by the politicians and bureaucrats in
Washington.
Although largely forgotten by historians and by the
public, repudiation of public debt is a solid part of the American tradition.
The first wave of repudiation of state debt came during the 1840s, after the
panics of 1837 and 1839. Those panics were the consequence of a massive
inflationary boom fueled by the Whig-run Second Bank of the United States.
Riding the wave of inflationary credit, numerous state governments, largely
those run by the Whigs, floated an enormous amount of debt, most of which went
into wasteful public works (euphemistically called "internal
improvements"), and into the creation of inflationary banks. Outstanding
public debt by state governments rose from $26 million to $170 million during
the decade of the 1830s. Most of these securities were financed by British and
Dutch investors.
During the deflationary 1840s succeeding the panics,
state governments faced repayment of their debt in dollars that were now more
valuable than the ones they had borrowed. Many states, now largely in
Democratic hands, met the crisis by repudiating these debts, either totally or
partially by scaling down the amount in "readjustments."
Specifically, of the 28 American states in the 1840s, 9 were in the glorious
position of having no public debt, and 1 (Missouri's) was negligible; of the 18
remaining, 9 paid the interest on their public debt without interruption, while
another 9 (Maryland, Pennsylvania, Indiana, Illinois, Michigan, Arkansas, Louisiana,
Mississippi, and Florida) repudiated part or all of their liabilities. Of these
states, four defaulted for several years in their interest payments, whereas
the other five (Michigan, Mississippi, Arkansas, Louisiana, and Florida)
totally and permanently repudiated their entire outstanding public debt. As in
every debt repudiation, the result was to lift a great burden from the backs of
the taxpayers in the defaulting and repudiating states.
Apart from the moral, or sanctity-of-contract argument
against repudiation that we have already discussed, the standard economic
argument is that such repudiation is disastrous, because who, in his right
mind, would lend again to a repudiating government? But the effective
counterargument has rarely been considered: why should more private capital be
poured down government rat holes? It is precisely the drying up of future
public credit that constitutes one of the main arguments for repudiation, for
it means beneficially drying up a major channel for the wasteful destruction of
the savings of the public. What we want is abundant savings and investment in
private enterprises, and a lean, austere, low-budget, minimal government. The
people and the economy can only wax fat and prosperous when their government is
starved and puny.
The next great wave of state debt repudiation came in
the South after the blight of Northern occupation and Reconstruction had been
lifted from them. Eight Southern states (Alabama, Arkansas, Florida, Louisiana,
North Carolina, South Carolina, Tennessee, and Virginia) proceeded, during the
late 1870s and early 1880s under Democratic regimes, to repudiate the debt
foisted upon their taxpayers by the corrupt and wasteful carpetbag Radical
Republican governments under Reconstruction.
So what can be done now? The current federal debt is
$3.5 trillion. Approximately $1.4 trillion, or 40 percent, is owned by one or
another agency of the federal government. It is ridiculous for a citizen to be
taxed by one arm of the federal government (the IRS) to pay interest and
principal on debt owned by another agency of the federal government. It would
save the taxpayer a great deal of money, and spare savings from further waste,
to simply cancel that debt outright. The alleged debt is simply an accounting
fiction that provides a mask over reality and furnishes a convenient means for
mulcting the taxpayer. Thus, most people think that the Social Security
Administration takes their premiums and accumulates it, perhaps by sound
investment, and then "pays back" the "insured" citizen when
he turns 65. Nothing could be further from the truth. There is no insurance and
there is no "fund," as there indeed must be in any system of private
insurance. The federal government simply takes the Social Security "premiums"
(taxes) of the young person, spends them in the general expenditures of the
Treasury, and then, when the person turns 65, taxes someone else to pay the
"insurance benefit." Social Security, perhaps the most revered
institution in the American polity, is also the greatest single racket. It's
simply a giant Ponzi scheme controlled by the federal government. But this
reality is masked by the Social Security Administration's purchase of
government bonds, the Treasury then spending these funds on whatever it wishes.
But the fact that the SSA has government bonds in its portfolio, and collects
interest and payment from the American taxpayer, allows it to masquerade as a
legitimate insurance business.
Canceling federal agency-held bonds, then, reduces the
federal debt by 40 percent. I would advocate going on to repudiate the entire
debt outright, and let the chips fall where they may. The glorious result would
be an immediate drop of $200 billion in federal expenditures, with at least the
fighting chance of an equivalent cut in taxes.
But if this scheme is considered too draconian, why
not treat the federal government as any private bankrupt is treated (forgetting
about Chapter 11)? The government is an organization, so why not liquidate the
assets of that organization and pay the creditors (the government bondholders)
a pro-rata share of those assets? This solution would cost the taxpayer
nothing, and, once again, relieve him of $200 billion in annual interest
payments. The United States government should be forced to disgorge its assets,
sell them at auction, and then pay off the creditors accordingly. What
government assets? There are a great deal of assets, from TVA to the national
lands to various structures such as the Post Office. The massive CIA
headquarters at Langley, Virginia, should raise a pretty penny for enough
condominium housing for the entire work force inside the Beltway. Perhaps we
could eject the United Nations from the United States, reclaim the land and
buildings, and sell them for luxury housing for the East Side gliterati.
Another serendipity out of this process would be a massive privatization of the
socialized land of the western United States and of the rest of America as
well. This combination of repudiation and privatization would go a long way to
reducing the tax burden, establishing fiscal soundness, and desocializing the
United States.
In order to go this route, however, we first have to
rid ourselves of the fallacious mindset that conflates public and private, and
that treats government debt as if it were a productive contract between two
legitimate property owners.
No comments:
Post a Comment