By Pierre Manent
We have been modern for several
centuries now. We are modern, and we want to be modern; it is
a desire that guides the entire life of Western societies. That the will to be
modern has been in force for centuries, though, suggests that we have not succeeded in
being truly modern—that the end of the process that we thought we saw coming at
various moments has always proved illusory, and that 1789, 1917, 1968, and 1989
were only disappointing steps along a road leading who knows where. The
Israelites were lucky: they wandered for only 40 years in the desert. If the
will to be modern has ceaselessly overturned the conditions of our common life
and brought one revolution after another—without achieving satisfaction or
reaching a point where we might rest and say, “Here at last is the end of our
enterprise”—just what does that mean? How have we been able to will something
for such a long time and accept being so often disappointed? Could it be that
we aren’t sure what we want? Though the various signs of the modern are
familiar, whether in architecture, art, science, or political organization, we
do not know what these traits have in common and what justifies designating
them with the same attribute. We find ourselves under the sway of something
that seems evident yet defies explication.
Some are inclined to give up
asking what we might call the question of the modern. They contend that we have
left the modern age and entered the postmodern, renouncing all “grand
narratives” of Western progress. I am not so sure, though, that we have
renounced the grand modern narratives of science and democracy. We may be
experiencing a certain fatigue with the modern after so many modern centuries,
but the question of the modern remains, and its urgency does not depend on the
disposition of the questioner. So long as self-understanding matters to us, the
question must be raised anew. Even if we do not claim to provide a new answer,
we should at least have the ambition to bring the question back to life.
When unsure about the nature of something, we sometimes ask when and how it began. Such an approach is legitimate when investigating the question of the modern, but it immediately raises difficulties. Beginnings are, by definition, obscure. The first sprouts are difficult to discern. One can easily be mistaken. In what time period should we look for the beginnings of modernity? In the eighteenth century, the age of the American and French Revolutions? In the seventeenth century, when the notion of natural science was elaborated? In the sixteenth century, the era of religious reformation? These diverse origins are not contradictory, since modernity surely includes a religious reformation, science in the modern sense, and political and democratic revolutions. But what is the relationship between the Lutheran faith and the science of Galileo? Is there a primary intellectual and moral disposition that defines modern man? Or must we resign ourselves to the dispersion of the elements of modernity, which we would then see as held together only by the magic of a word?
When unsure about the nature of something, we sometimes ask when and how it began. Such an approach is legitimate when investigating the question of the modern, but it immediately raises difficulties. Beginnings are, by definition, obscure. The first sprouts are difficult to discern. One can easily be mistaken. In what time period should we look for the beginnings of modernity? In the eighteenth century, the age of the American and French Revolutions? In the seventeenth century, when the notion of natural science was elaborated? In the sixteenth century, the era of religious reformation? These diverse origins are not contradictory, since modernity surely includes a religious reformation, science in the modern sense, and political and democratic revolutions. But what is the relationship between the Lutheran faith and the science of Galileo? Is there a primary intellectual and moral disposition that defines modern man? Or must we resign ourselves to the dispersion of the elements of modernity, which we would then see as held together only by the magic of a word?
Let us start with the one
incontestable point in the perplexities just laid out: that we have wanted, and
continue to want, to be modern. It is not necessary to know exactly what we
want in order to know that, in so wanting, we form a project.
Modernity is, first of all, a collective project—formulated in Europe and first
applied there but destined for humanity as a whole.
To form a great collective
project, ultimately destined for all humanity, demands great faith in one’s own
powers. There is something striking in this regard about the beginnings of
modern science: Bacon and Descartes, to name just two pioneers, showed
extraordinary confidence in the capacity of the new science radically to
transform the conditions of human life. What faith—what blind faith—they had,
one is tempted to say! For modern science had yet to produce any of its
miracles. Descartes, for example, imagined medicine’s prodigiously lengthening
human life at a time when it was incapable of curing anything.
Inherent in the idea of a
project are the beliefs that we are capable of acting and that our action can
transform the conditions of our life. Many analysts of modernity have insisted
on the second point, the transformative or constructive ambition of the modern
project. But we must not pass over the first point too quickly. We are capable
of acting—a world is contained in those words! Human beings have always acted
in some way, but they have not always known that they were
capable of acting. There is something terrible in human action: what makes us
human is also what exposes us, takes us out of ourselves, and sometimes causes
us to lose ourselves. In the beginning, human beings gathered, fished, hunted,
or even made war, which is a kind of hunting; but they acted as little as
possible, leaving much to the gods and tying themselves down with prohibitions,
rites, and sacred restraints. Historically, properly human action first appears
as crime or transgression. This, according to Hegel, is what Greek tragedy
brings to light: innocently criminal action. Tragedy recounts the passage from
what precedes action to properly human action.
So modernity may be described
as a project of collective action—and the great domain of action is politics,
which is action ordered and implemented. It follows that the modern project
must be understood in the first instance as a political project; we must
situate it, therefore, in the history of European and Western political
development.
Modernity is characterized by movement,
a movement that never reaches its end or comes to rest. There are great
civilizations other than the West, and much has happened in them, but they have
not known historical movement. They have chronicles but not a history—at least
before the pressure or aggression of the West brought them into history. In the
West, by contrast, one finds a singular principle of movement, and this is what
characterizes it above all.
The movement of the West began
with the movement of the Greek city. Some have said that the Greeks ignored
history, that they had a cyclical understanding of time, and that time oriented
by history began with Christianity, if not with the modern philosophy of
history. That contention does not hold up. The Greeks were well acquainted with
the irreversible time of political history. Aristotle was just as capable as
Tocqueville of observing that, in his age, democracy was the only regime still
possible.
To be more precise, Western
movement began with internal and external movements of the Greek city—that is,
with class struggle and foreign war. Cities were the ordering of human life that
brought to light the domain of the common, the government of what was common,
and the implementation of the common. The Greek city was the first complete
implementation of human action, the ordering of the human world that made
action possible and meaningful, the place where men for the first time
deliberated and formulated projects of action. It was there that men discovered
that they could govern themselves and that they learned to do it. The Greek
city was the first form of human life to produce political energy—a deployment
of human energy of a new intensity and quality. It was finally consumed by its
own energy in the catastrophe of the Peloponnesian War.
Subsequent Western history
was, on the whole, an ever-renewed search for a political form that would
recover the energies of the city while escaping the fate of the city—the city
that is free but destined to internal and external enmity. The form that
followed the city was the empire. Imperial Rome was a kind of continuation of
the city, but it deployed such powerful energies that it broke through all
limits that had circumscribed cities and took in ever more distant and numerous
populations, until it seemed to reach the point of gathering together the
entire human race. The Roman Empire renounced the city’s freedom but promised
unity and peace.
This promise was not kept, of
course, or it was kept incompletely. However, as in the case of the city,
political and spiritual energies partially survived the failure of the form.
Not only did the imperial idea mark the West through the enduring prestige of
the Roman Empire; the idea was reborn in a new form, one that was, again,
particular to Europe. This was the Catholic or universal Church, which aimed to
reunite all mankind in a new communion, closer than that of the most enclosed
city and more extensive than that of the vastest empire. Of all the political
forms of the West, the Church extended the greatest promises, since it proposed
this community, at once city and empire; but it was also the most disappointing,
since it failed to bring about the universal association for which it had
awakened a desire.
Though I have just surveyed
the history of premodern Europe with the speed and delicacy of Attila the Hun,
I have gathered the elements of the situation that will allow me to elaborate
the modern project. Europeans were divided among the city, the empire, and the
Church. They lived under these mixed and competing authorities, these three
modes of human association. The cities that survived or were reborn were in
competition with—indeed, often at war with—the Roman Empire (now known as the
Holy Roman Empire, in what is today Germany); and the Church was in competition
with the cities and the empire, which, in turn, were in competition with it.
The disorder was dreadful, a conflict of authorities and of loyalty. It was
this confusion that the modern project wanted to allow us to escape—and in
this, it succeeded.
The conflicts had to do with
institutions but also, more profoundly, with the human type that would inspire
European life. Whom to imitate? Did one have to follow the life of humble
sacrifice for which Christ provided the model? Or was it better to lead the
proud, active life of the warrior-citizen, a life for which Rome had provided
the framework and of which Rome was the product par excellence? Should
Europeans, surveying the ancient world, admire Cato or Caesar? Europeans no
longer knew which city they wanted, or were able, to inhabit; thus they did not
know what kind of human being they wanted, or were able, to be. It was in this
radical perplexity, and in order to come to terms with it, that the modern
project was born.
Finding themselves assailed by
prestigious and contradictory authorities—words of the Bible, words of Greek
philosophers, words of Roman historians and orators—the Europeans did not know
which to follow and which to dismiss. Thus, they did not know how to act; they
did not know how to respond to the question, What is to be done? Speech and
action were disjoined.
The modern moment crystallized
in the effort to attach speech to action more rigorously. This was the work of
the Reformation. The authority of the Word of God had been divided between the
Scriptures and Church tradition—but the Scriptures were accessible only through
the mediation of the Church and in Latin, the language of the Church. Martin
Luther wanted to attach Christian faith immediately to the Word of God as found
in the Scriptures by rejecting the mediation of ecclesiastical authority and
translating the sacred text into the language spoken and understood by the
faithful. Sola scriptura, said the Reformers: Scripture alone.
It was Machiavelli, however,
who—at exactly the same time as Luther—formulated in the most general terms
what lay at the heart of the problem and what would be the principle of the
political solution. Both problem and solution appear in Chapter 15 of The
Prince:
But since my intent is to
write something useful to whoever understands it, it has appeared to me more
fitting to go directly to the effectual truth of the thing than to the
imagination of it. And many have imagined republics and principalities that
have never been seen or known to exist in truth; for it is so far from how one
lives to how one should live that he who lets go of what is done for what
should be done learns his ruin rather than his preservation.
The reason that Machiavelli
decided to write about the way men actually lived, not the way they behaved in
those imaginary “republics and principalities,” was the great distance, which
we have just noted, between what men said and what they did.
Now, the greatest distance
between speech and action is introduced by the Christian Word, which requires
men to love what they naturally hate (their enemies) and to hate what they
naturally love (themselves). The modern political project, which Machiavelli
was the first to formulate, was therefore a response—it began as a response, in
any case—to the “Christian situation,” one marked by competition among
authorities, disorder of references, anarchy of words, and, above all, the
demoralizing contrast between what men said and what they did.
What did Machiavelli mean by
considering the “effectual truth of the thing”? He intended to prepare the way
for a kind of action entirely liberated from speech, religious or otherwise,
that praised or blamed—a kind of action that no speech could fetter, whether
the external speech of an institution or opinion or the internal speech of
conscience. The speech that has the most weight and that tends most to fetter
action is: “This is good, that is bad.” Machiavelli did not seek to nullify
this distinction; he did not confuse good and bad. Rather, he encouraged men to
prepare themselves to do what was bad, to “enter into the bad,” as he wrote,
when necessary. Machiavelli strove to break down the barrier formed by the
words that tell us what we should do—which, he believed, give us little
guidance, since we follow our natures and not our words, but which nevertheless
constrain our freedom of action by limiting the field of possible or
conceivable action.
It is difficult to say
concretely what new political order Machiavelli imagined. One can say
that by delivering human beings from respect for opinion, he prepared them for
all possible actions, including the most audacious, the most ambitious, and
even the most terrible.
Among the audacious and
ambitious actions that have taken place in the theater of Europe, the modern
state has conducted the most decisive. As we have seen, Christianity rendered
the motives of human action uncertain and the speech that must be authoritative
in the city doubtful. The modern state became sovereign by resolving or
overcoming that conflict, by taking upon itself the monopoly of authoritative
speech—or, more precisely, by producing commandments independent of all opinion
(including all religious opinion), commandments that authorized or forbade
opinions according to the state’s sovereign decision. At first, it is true, the
state, uncertain of its strength, associated itself with religious opinion or
speech—with a state religion. As it grew stronger, however, it forbade less and
less speech and authorized more and more. Once it reached its full strength, it
lifted itself above speech, becoming the “neutral,” “agnostic,” or “secular”
state that we know so well.
But the modern secular state
was only half of the solution to the problem of the gap between speech and
action in the Christian world, precisely because a condition of its
effectiveness was that it had no speech of its own. Yet there can be no human
life without authoritative speech. Where would the modern state find such
speech? It found it in society—by becoming “representative” of society.
Representation joined society’s speech to the action of a state lacking its own
speech.
The problem of the Christian
age was solved, therefore, by the sovereign state and by representative
government—that is, by our political regime considered as a whole. My object
here is not to describe the mechanisms or, for that matter, to sketch the
history of the representative regime. Still, one point must be emphasized. The
decisive factor in the reconciliation between speech and action is the
formation of a common speech by the elaboration, perfection, and diffusion of a national language.
Luther’s Reformation was a spiritual upheaval, but it was also inseparably a
political revolution and a national insurrection. Too often forgotten is that
even before the modern state was consolidated and became capable of authorizing
or prohibiting effectively, the nation had emerged in Europe
as the setting for the appropriation of the Christian Word, which the universal
Church had proved incapable of teaching effectively. Each European nation chose
the Christian confession under which it wished to live and essentially imposed
it, after many attempts, on its “sovereign.” Europe assumed its classic form
with the “confessional nation,” soon to be crowned by its absolute sovereign,
who would later bring about its “secularization”; and this was the form in
which it succeeded in organizing itself in the most stable and durable manner.
From then on, it was in the framework of a national civic conversation
that Europeans sought to link their speech with their actions and their actions
with their speech. The national form preceded and conditioned representative
government.
So the history of the West
unfolded in tension between, on the one hand, the civic operation—which the
Greek city brought to light, and which the republican or “Roman” tradition
sought to preserve and extend—and, on the other, the Christian Word, which
opened up an unmanageable gap between speech and action in political society by
proposing a new city where actions and speech might achieve an unprecedented
unity, where we might live according to the Word. The practical solution was
found in the nation distinguished by its confession, administered by a secular
state, and governed by a representative government. The solution has neither
the energizing simplicity of the civic form nor the ambitious precision of the
ecclesiastical form. And the West will ceaselessly seek a final, complete
solution that would bring together the energy of the civic operation and the
precision of the religious proposition. The regimes that we call “totalitarian”
are those capable of bringing together the most unbridled and terrible action
with the most pedantic ideological and linguistic orthodoxy. Do we not see in
such regimes the monstrous but altogether recognizable expression of the quest
for such a final solution?
Today in Europe, civic
activity is feeble, the religious Word almost inaudible. Yet as we noted at the
outset, the modern project continues. Is it merely running on its own inertia,
or is the ceaseless quest that I have just described still going on? To answer
that question, it may be useful to offer a description of Europe’s present
situation concerning the relationship between speech and action.
A frequent criticism of
representative democracy or of parliamentary regimes is that they produce lots
of talk but are incapable of action. Marx spoke of “parliamentary cretinism,”
for example, and Carl Schmitt liked to cite Donoso Cortés’s sarcasms against
the bourgeoisie, a clase discutidora—an “argumentative class.” In
reality, however, a functioning representative democracy or parliamentary
regime constitutes an admirable articulation of actions in relation to speech.
During an electoral campaign, everyone proposes all sorts of imaginable
actions, both possible and impossible. As soon as the election is over, those
who have won the majority undertake to act according to their speech, while the
minority, abstaining from action, must satisfy itself with talk in order to
prepare for the next election. This transference back and forth of power, or
the effective possibility of such transference, is essential to the mechanism.
In Europe, this arrangement
has weakened considerably and is now almost unrecognizable. We congratulate
ourselves for the attenuation of party conflict while oddly treating transfers
of power as matters of momentous importance. The political landscape has been
leveled. The webs of feelings, opinions, and language that once made up political
convictions have unraveled. It is no longer possible to gain political ground
by taking a position. This is why all political actors tend to use all
political languages indiscriminately.
Political speech has become
increasingly removed from any essential relation to a possible action. The
notion of a political program, reduced to that of “promises,” has been
discredited. The explicit or implicit conviction that one has no choice has
become widespread: what will be done will be determined by circumstances beyond
our control. Political speech no longer aims to prepare a possible action but
tries simply to cover conscientiously the range of political speech. Everyone,
or almost everyone, admits that the final meeting between action and speech
will be no more than a meeting of independent causal chains.
The divorce between action and
speech helps explain the new role of political correctness. Because speech is
no longer tied to a possible and plausible action against which we might
measure it, many take speech as seriously as if it were itself an action and
consider speech they do not like equivalent to the worst possible action.
Offending forms of speech are tracked down and labeled, in the language of
pathologists, “phobias.” The progress of freedom in the West once consisted of
measuring speech by the standard of visible actions; political correctness
consists of measuring speech by the standard of invisible intentions.
The features of our political
situation that I have highlighted are found in all Western countries but in an
especially pronounced form in contemporary Europe. In Europe, what we say as
citizens no longer has any importance, since political actions will be decided
at some indeterminate place, a place we cannot situate in relation to the standpoint
from which we speak. Everyone knows that the most solemn speech that a people
can formulate, a vote by referendum, is a matter of indifference for the
European political class, which charges itself with the responsibility of
leading the necessary process of the “construction” of a united Europe. The
supposed necessity of this process discredits and invalidates all political
speech in advance.
If this process continues—the
financial crisis of the euro has put extraordinary pressure on it—we will soon
leave behind the regime of representative government and return to one of
speechless commandment. The commandment will no longer be that of the state,
which at least occupied a place of a certain elevation, but that of
regulations. We do not know the source of regulations—only that we must obey
them.
With the end or the weakening
of the representative regime, which once joined actions and speech in the
national framework, the modern political order is approaching the end of its
journey. We are witnessing a deeper divorce between the movement of
civilization and our political arrangements. The increasingly complex and
constraining character of ordinary life and the tighter network of regulations
that we obey with ever-greater docility must not blind us to the increasing
uncertainty—the increasing disorder—in the shape of our common life. We are
going forward on thinning ice.
In fact, we may be returning
to a situation of political indetermination comparable, in a sense, with what
preceded the construction of modern politics. Yet there is a major difference.
During the premodern era, competing political forms—the city, the empire, and
the Church—checked one another, so it was necessary to create the unprecedented
form of the nation. Today, the situation is reversed. What we find is not an
excess, but a dearth, of political forms. At least in Europe, the nation is
discredited and delegitimized, but no other form is emerging. What is more, the
reigning opinion, practically the sole available opinion, has been hammering
into us for 20 years the idea that the future belongs to a delocalized and
globalized process of civilization and that we do not need a political form.
Thus, the need for a political joining of speech to action has been lost to
view. Technical norms and legal regulations are supposed to suffice for the
organization of common life.
Europe produced modernity—and
for a long time, Europe was the master and possessor of modernity, putting it
to the almost exclusive service of its own power. But this transformative
project was inherently destined for humanity as a whole. Today, Bacon and
Descartes rule in Shanghai and Bangalore at least as much as in London and
Paris. Europe finds itself militarily, politically, and spiritually disarmed in
a world that it has armed with the means of modern civilization. Soon it will
be wholly incapable of defending itself. It has already been incapable of
speaking up for itself for a long time, since it confuses itself with a
humanity on the path to pacification and unification.
By renouncing the political
form that was its own and by which it had attempted, with some success, to
resolve the European problem, Europe has deprived itself of the means of
association in which its life had found the richest meaning, diffracted in a multiplicity
of national languages that rivaled one another in strength and in grace. What will come next?
No comments:
Post a Comment