For Marx mankind, led by a vanguard of secular saints, would establish a secularized kingdom of heaven on earth
by Murray N. Rothbard,
[This article is excerpted from volume 2, chapter 10
of An Austrian
Perspective on the History of Economic Thought (1995)
The key to the intricate and massive system of thought
created by Karl Marx (1818–83) is at bottom a simple one: Karl Marx was a communist. A seemingly banal or trite
statement set alongside Marxism's myriad of jargon-ridden concepts in
philosophy, economics, history, culture, etc. Yet Marx's devotion to communism
was his crucial point, far more central than the dialectic, the class struggle,
the theory of surplus value, and all the rest. Communism was the goal, the
great end, the desideratum, the ultimate end that would make the sufferings of
mankind throughout history worthwhile. History is the history of suffering, of
class struggle, of the exploitation of man by man. In the same way as the
return of the Messiah, in Christian theology, would put an end to history and
establish a new heaven and a new earth, so the establishment of communism would
put an end to human history. And just as for postmillennial Christians, man,
led by God's prophets and saints, would establish a Kingdom of God on earth
(and, for premillennials, Jesus would have many human assistants in
establishing such a Kingdom), so for Marx and other schools of communists, mankind,
led by a vanguard of secular saints, would establish a secularized kingdom of
heaven on earth.
In messianic religious movements, the millennium is
invariably established by a mighty, violent upheaval, an Armageddon, a great
apocalyptic war between good and evil. After this titanic conflict, a
millennium, a new age, of peace and harmony, a reign of justice, would be
established upon the earth.
Marx emphatically rejected those utopians who aimed to
arrive at communism through a gradual and evolutionary process, through a
steady advancement of the good. No, Marx harked back to the apocalyptics, the
postmillennial coercive German and Dutch Anabaptists of the 16th century, to
the millennial sects during the English Civil War, and to the various groups of
premillennial Christians who foresaw a bloody Armageddon at the Last Days,
before the millennium could be established. Indeed, since the immediatist
postmils refused to wait for gradual goodness and sainthood to permeate among
men, they joined the premils in believing that only a violent apocalyptic final
struggle between good and evil, between saints and sinners, could establish the
millennium. Violent, worldwide revolution, in Marx's version made by the
oppressed proletariat, would be the instrument of the advent of his millennium,
communism.
In fact, Marx, like the premils (or
"millenarians") went further to hold that the reign of evil on earth
would reach a peak just before the apocalypse. For Marx as for the
millenarians, writes Ernest Tuveson,
The evil of the world must proceed to its height before, in one great complete root-and-branch upheaval, it would be swept away.…
Millenarian pessimism about the perfectibility of the existing world is crossed by a supreme optimism. History, the millenarian believes, so operates that, when evil has reached its height, the hopeless situation will be reversed. The original, the true harmonious state of society, in some kind of egalitarian order, will be reestablished.[1]
But certain features are broadly alike in all visions
of communism. Private property is eliminated, individualism goes by the board,
individuality is flattened, all property is owned and controlled communally,
and the individual units of the new collective organism are in some vague way
equal to one another.
This millennialist emphasis on the collective is a
long way from the orthodox Christian, Augustinian stress on the individual soul
and his salvation. In orthodox, amillennial Christianity, the individual does
or does not achieve salvation, until Jesus returns and puts an end to history,
and ushers in the Day of Judgment. There is no millennium on earth; the Kingdom
of God remains safely, and appropriately, in heaven. But millennialism's
emphasis on achieving a Kingdom of God on earth inevitably
stressed — especially in the required human agency of the postmillennialists —
the inevitable collective march toward the Kingdom in and through history. In
what we may call the "immediatist" version of postmil doctrine, as we
have seen in Volume 1 in the Brethren of the Free Spirit, the coercive
Anabaptists of the Reformation, in Christian communists and in a secularized
version in Marxism, the object is to seize immediate power in a violent
revolution, and to purge the world of sinners and heretics, i.e., all who are
not followers of the sect in question, so as to establish the millennium, the
precondition of Jesus's Second Advent. In contrast, the gradualist postmils, in less violent and
precipitate fashion, who would seize control of most of the Protestant churches
in the northern United States during the 19th century, wanted to use state
power to coerce morality and virtue and then establish the Kingdom of God, not
only in the United States, but throughout the world. As one historian
penetratingly concludes about one of the most prominent postmil economists and
social scientists of the late 19th century — a passage that could apply to the
entire movement:
In [Richard T.] Ely's eyes, government was the
God-given instrument through which we had to work. Its preeminence as a divine
instrument was based on the post-Reformation abolition of the division between
the sacred and the secular and on the State's power to implement ethical
solutions to public problems. The same identification of sacred and secular …
enabled Ely to both divinize the state and socialize Christianity: he thought
of government as God's major instrument of redemption … [2]
Gradualists or immediatists, all millennialists have
caused grave social and political trouble by "immanentizing the
eschaton" — in the political philosopher Eric Voegelin's infelicitously
worded but highly perceptive phrase. As an orthodox Christian, Voegelin
believed that "the eschaton" — the Final Days, the Kingdom of God —
must be kept strictly out of earthly matters and be confined to the
other-worldly realms of heaven and hell. But to take the "eschaton"
out of heaven and bring it down into the processes of human history, is to
create grave problems and consequences: consequences which Voegelin saw
embodied in such immanent and messianic movements as Marxism and Nazism.
In common with other utopian socialists and
communists, Marx sought in communism the apotheosis of the collective species —
mankind as one new super-being, in which the only meaning possessed by the
individual is as a negligible particle of that collective organism. One
incisive portrayal of Marxian collective organicism — what amounts to a
celebration of the New Socialist Man to be created during the communizing
process — was that of a top Bolshevik theoretician of the early 20th century,
Alexander Alexandravich Bogdanov (1873–1928). Bogdanov, like Joachim of Fiore,
spoke of "three ages" of human history: first was a religious,
authoritarian society and a self-sufficient economy. Next came the "second
age," an exchange economy, marked by diversity and the emergence of
"autonomy" of the "individual human personality." But this
individualism, at first progressive, later becomes an obstacle to progress as
it hampers and "contradicts the unifying tendencies of the machine
age." But then there will arise the third age, the final stage of history,
communism, though not as with Joachim, an age of the Holy Spirit. This last
stage will be marked by a collective self-sufficient economy, and by the fusion
of personal lives into one colossal whole, harmonious in the relations of its
parts, systematically grouping all elements for one common struggle — struggle
against the endless spontaneity of nature … An enormous mass of creative
activity … is necessary in order to solve this task. It demands the forces not
of man but of mankind — and only in working at this task does mankind as such
emerge.[3]
The acme of messianic communism appears in the
frenzied three-volume phantasmagoria by the notable German blend of Christian
messianist and Marxist-Leninist-Stalinist, Ernst Bloch (1885–1977). Bloch held
that the "inner truth" of things could only be discovered after
"a complete transformation of the universe, a grand apocalypse, the
descent of the Messiah, a new heaven, and a new earth." As J.P. Stern
writes in his review of Bloch's three-volume Principle of Hope, the
book contains such remarkable declamations as Ubi Lenin, ibi Jerusalem ("Where
Lenin is, there is Jerusalem"), and that "the Bolshevist fulfillment
of Communism" is part and parcel of "the age-old fight for God."
There is also more than a hint, in Bloch, that disease, nay even death itself,
will be abolished upon the advent of communism.[4]
In contrast, there is no more eloquent championing of
orthodox Christian individualism and revulsion against collectivism, than G.K. Chesterton's
critique of the views of a leading Fabian socialist, Mrs. Annie Besant — in
which Chesterton swats Mrs. Besant's pantheistic Buddhism:
“According to Mrs Besant the universal Church is
simply the universal Self. It is the doctrine that we are really all one
person; that there are no real walls of individuality between man and man.… She
does not tell us to love our neighbor; she tells us to be our neighbors … the
intellectual abyss between Buddhism and Christianity is that, for the Buddhist
or theosophist, personality is the fall of man, for the Christian it is the
purpose of God, the whole point of his cosmic idea”.[5]
Let us turn to some of the main features of communism.
In the typical communal millennial future, an epoch of bliss and harmony, work, the necessity to labor, becomes deemphasized
or disappears altogether. Labor, at least labor in order to maintain and
advance one's living standards, does not ring true with very many people as a
feature of utopia. Thus, in the vision of Joachim of Fiore, perhaps the first
medieval millennialist, no work would be required to disturb the endless round
of celebration and prayer, because mankind would have achieved the status of immaterial
objects. If man were pure spirit, it is true that the economic problem — the
problem of production and living standards — would necessarily disappear.
Unfortunately, however, Marx, being an atheist and materialist, could not
exactly fall back on a Fiore-like communism of pure spirit. How could solidly
material human beings solve the problem of production and of maintaining and
expanding their living standards?
There was method in Marx's refusal to treat the
communist stage in any detail. His utopia was shadowy. On the one hand, Marx
assumed and asserted that goods in the future communist society would be
superabundant. If so, there would of course be no need to refer to the
universal economic problem of scarcity of means and resources as applied to
ends. But by assuming away the problem, Marx bequeathed the puzzle to future
generations, and Marxists have been split on the question: Will communism
itself bring about this magical state of superabundance, or should we wait until capitalism brings superabundance before we
establish communism? Generally, Marxist groups have solved this problem, not in
theory but in practice (or "praxis"), by cleaving to whatever path
would allow them either to conquer or to maintain their power. Thus Marxist vanguards
or parties, on seeing an opportunity to seize power, have been invariably
willing to skip the "stages of history" preordained by their Master
and exercise their revolutionary will. On the other hand, Marxist elites
already entrenched in power have prudentially put off the ultimate goal of
communism ever further into a receding future. And so the Soviets were quick to
stress hard work and gradualism in persevering toward the ultimate goal.[6]
There are several other probable reasons for Marx's
failure to detail the features of ultimate communism, or, indeed, of the
necessary stages to achieve it. First is that Marx had no interest in the
economic features of his utopia; a simple question-begging assumption of
unlimited abundance was enough. His main interest, as we shall see, was in the
philosophic, indeed religious, aspects of communism. Second, communism for Marx
was an inverted form of Hegel and his philosophy of history; it was the
revolutionary end to Marx's neo-Hegelian version of "alienation" and
of the "dialectic" process by which the aufhebung (transcendence) and negation of one
historical stage is replaced by another and opposing one. In this case: the
negation of the evil condition of private property and the division of labor,
and the establishment of communism, in which man's unity with man and nature is
achieved. To Marx, as to Hegel, history necessarily proceeds by this magical
dialectic, in which one stage gives rise inevitably to a later and opposing
stage. Except that to Marx, the "dialectic" is material rather than
spiritual.[7] Marx never published his neo-Hegelian Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, in
which the philosophic basis of Marxism was set forth, and one essay of which,
"Private Property and Communism," contained Marx's fullest exposition
of the communist society. One reason for his refusal to publish was that, in
later decades, Hegelian philosophy had gone out of fashion, even in Germany,
and Marx's followers were interested more in the economic and revolutionary
aspects of Marxism.
Notes
[1] Ernest L. Tuveson, "The Millenarian
Structure of The Communist Manifesto," in
C.A. Patrides and Joseph Wittreich (eds), The Apocalypse: in English
Renaissance Thought and Literature (Ithaca: Cornell University
Press, 1984), pp. 326–7. Tuveson speculates that Marx and Engels may have been
influenced by the outburst of millenarianism in England during the 1840s. On
this phenomenon, particularly the flare-up in England and the US of the
Millerites, who predicted the end of the world on 22 October 1844, see the
classic work on modern millenarianism, Ernest R. Sandeen, The Roots of Fundamentalism: British and American Millenarianism,
1800–1930 (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1970). See Tuveson, ibid., p. 340, n. 5.
[2] Jean B. Quandt, "Religion and Social
Thought: The Secularization of Postmillennialism," American Quarterly,25 (Oct. 1973), pp. 402–3. Actually,
Ely, in common with many other postmils, was not all that gradual, as he spoke of the New Jerusalem,
"which we are all eagerly awaiting."
[3] Quoted in S.V. Utechin, "Philosophy and
Society: Alexander Bogdanov," in Leopold Labedz (ed.). Revisionism: Essays on the History of Marxist Ideas (New
York: Praeger, 1962), p. 122.
[4] J.P. Stern, "Marxism on Stilts: Review of
Ernst Bloch, The Principle of Hope," The New Republic, 196
(9 March 1987), pp. 40, 42; Leszek Kolakowski, Main
Currents of Marxism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984),
III, pp. 423–4.
[5] G.K. Chesterton, Orthodoxy (New
York: 1927), pp. 244–5. Quoted in Thomas Molnar, Utopia: the Perennial Heresy (New York: Sheed
& Ward, 1964), p. 123.
[6] "The C.P.S.U. [Communist Party of the Soviet
Union], being a party of scientific communism, advances and solves the problems
of communist construction as the material and spiritual prerequisites for them
become ready and mature, being guided by the fact that necessary stages of
development must not be skipped over … ."Fundamentals of Marxism — Leninism (2nd rev. ed., Moscow: Foreign Languages
Publishing House, 1963), p. 662. Also see ibid., pp. 645–6, 666–7, 674–5.
No comments:
Post a Comment