In 1789 a group of men gathered in Paris to sound the
death knell for the ancien regime, and
to inaugurate the modern political world. But there were some differences among
them. Some wanted to abolish the old order more completely. Others wanted to
retain some vestiges of the old privileges. In this "National Constituent
Assembly" of France, the ideological birds of a feather sat together: the
more radical members on the left, the more conservative members on the right.
On that day, on the eve of the French Revolution, not
only was the modern political world born, but so was its terminology.[1] To this day, politics is bisected into a
"left wing" and "right wing." Much digital ink is daily
spilled in vain on the web over the "best" distinction between
"right" and "left." Now, with regard to specific, fleeting
political agendas, vague distinctions like this make sense. Movable umbrella
terms are necessary, because legislation involves shifting coalitions of people
who do not agree on every single point. The trouble starts when the terminology
of the political moment is imported wholesale into the language of science, in
which precise, fixed distinctions are called for. The left/right divide is
downright confusing for social science.
Where this confusion is most pronounced is in
intellectual discussion of Western society following World War I. According to
common opinion, there are two politicoeconomic extremes: communism (or
socialism) on the left, and fascism (or Nazism) on the right. Sound policy,
then, is considered a balancing act between two opposite forms of
totalitarianism. If one leans too far to the left toward the interests of the
poor and weak, one arrives at communism/socialism. Veer too far to the right
toward the interests of the rich and strong, and you get fascism. This
political taxonomy is entirely unscientific. Neither fascism nor Nazism has
ever been scientifically identifiable social orders. They are party platforms,
and thus are assemblages of often-contradictory ideas and slogans. Calling
fascism a "social order" makes as little sense as calling "Tea
Partyism" or "Blue Dog Democrat-ism" a social order.
Moreover, as Ludwig von Mises demonstrated,[2] the allegedly "right-wing" social order of Nazi Germany was just as socialistic as was Lenin's Russia. Through economic interventions the German government completely took over the economy. The only "market" left was a sham. Private individuals owned the means of production in name only. Real ownership of the means of production was in the hands of the state. This is what Mises called "socialism of the German or Hindenburg pattern." This variety of socialism is also known as Zwangswirtschaft, which is basically German for "compulsory economy." Those who were once entrepreneurs devolve in a Zwangswirtschaft into mere shop managers (Betriebsfuhrer in Nazi legalese), following the orders of a central command.
Moreover, as Ludwig von Mises demonstrated,[2] the allegedly "right-wing" social order of Nazi Germany was just as socialistic as was Lenin's Russia. Through economic interventions the German government completely took over the economy. The only "market" left was a sham. Private individuals owned the means of production in name only. Real ownership of the means of production was in the hands of the state. This is what Mises called "socialism of the German or Hindenburg pattern." This variety of socialism is also known as Zwangswirtschaft, which is basically German for "compulsory economy." Those who were once entrepreneurs devolve in a Zwangswirtschaft into mere shop managers (Betriebsfuhrer in Nazi legalese), following the orders of a central command.
The only way in which "socialism of the Russian
or Lenin pattern" (as Mises termed the more familiar variant of socialism)
is distinct from the Zwangswirtschaft is
in the nonessential fact that it has no such veneer of faux-private ownership. Its socialism is simply more
overt.
Another way of stating this is as follows. In the
populist propaganda of Bolshevism, under "socialism of the Russian or
Lenin pattern" the people ostensibly own the state, and the state in turn
owns the means of production. While, under the sham capitalism of Nazism and
"socialism of the German or Hindenburg pattern," the people
ostensibly own the means of production, but the state in turn owns the people.
Thus these occupants of different political "poles"
really occupy the same ground and are only separated by a trivial technicality:
the existence or absence of a sham market. Each variant of socialism does
indeed have its own distinctive path. But it has nothing to do with "left
vs. right," "poor vs. rich," or "weak vs. powerful."
Rather, it is a matter of "bureaucratization vs. interventionism."
Bureaucratization, by forthrightly gobbling up the market bite by bite, leads
to the overt socialism of the Russian or Lenin pattern. Interventionism, by subtly
crippling the market and replacing it incrementally with a network of
government diktats, leads to the sham market of socialism of the German or
Hindenburg pattern.[3]
Revolutionary socialist governments, like the Nazi and
the Bolshevist states, will generally adopt one path or the other. But it is by
no means necessarily an either/or choice. Gradual approaches toward socialism,
like the one the United States is currently taking, often rely on both: overtly
socializing an industry via nationalization here and covertly socializing an
industry via market interventions there. And one type of socialization often
leads to the other. Thus through this gradual, dual approach to socialization,
one can imagine what one day might be called "socialism of the American
pattern" arising, characterized by a hodgepodge of vast bureaus and sham
markets.
Thus it is conceivable that there can be a single
socialist system that is a mixture of the two varieties of socialism. However,
a mixture of capitalism and socialism is entirely inconceivable, in spite of
the fact that most people think that all real-world societies have only ever
had "mixed economies."[4]
As Mises wrote, the mere existence of some bureaus and
state-owned firms does not alter the capitalist nature of society and make it a
"mixed system" of capitalism and socialism. Defining "economy"
as a social system of production, there is no such thing as a "mixed
economy." Bureaucracies in society are not an integral aspect of the
social system of production. They operate as (basically consumptive) elements
within a market economy. But they do not contribute any social coordination to
it. Rather, it is the market economy that contributes coordination to
bureaucracies, in that the latter wholly depend on market prices to be able to
attain even the severely impaired budget rationality characteristic of
bureaucratic management. The social system of production can only ever be
rationalized by market processes.[5] Even the crippled social production that occurred
in Lenin's Russia and Hitler's Germany was only possible because recourse could
be taken to the prices that formed in the surviving market processes of the
outside world. As Mises wrote in Human Action,
Soviet Russia and Nazi Germany … were not isolated
socialist systems. They were operating in an environment in which the price
system still worked. They could resort to economic calculation on the ground of
the prices established abroad.
This is why the actual economies of Lenin's Russia and
Hitler's Germany were referred to above as "socialistic" and not
"socialist."
Another important distinction is that, according to
Mises, bureaucratization is not a form of interventionism.[6] Bureaucratization makes people poorer to be
sure, but it does so by constraining the ambit of the market, not by
interfering in its workings.
Some have said "interventionism" is a system
in-and-of itself, and they propose it as a sensible,
"middle-of-the-road" policy between capitalism and socialism. Mises
exploded this fallacy. Utilizing the findings of classical political economy,
as well as the findings of modern economics (including his own original
insights), he demonstrated that all economic interventions are, in effect,
contrary to the purposes of all, including the purposes of those who advocate
them.[7] They are thus destructive, not constructive.
Interventionism is not a system of social production; it is nothing but a
hampering of capitalism. A hampered capitalist order is still a capitalist
order. The social system of production in a hampered capitalist order is always
rationalized by the sectors of the market that have not yet been crippled by
interventions.
When one is confronted by the contrary-to-purpose
effects of an intervention, one has two choices in dealing with those effects.
One can undo the intervention, in which case one chooses capitalism. Or one can
try to eliminate the harm with further intervention. However, further
intervention can only lead to still more harm, which would thus call for yet
further intervention, leading to a "cycle of interventionism." Thus,
if one does not choose capitalism, one must choose ever-increasing
interventions, which ultimately will completely destroy the market and
culminate in socialism of the German pattern.[8] If one does not choose capitalism, one chooses
socialism.
Not everybody associates "fascism" with the
economic policy of the Nazis. Those who know their history remember that part
of the economic policy platform of Benito Mussolini, the founder of fascism,
was "corporativism," in which production was directed by "corporatives,"
each of which represented the participants of a specific industry. Some even
call our present economic order "fascist," because they equate
"corporatism" with the "corporativism" that they identify with
fascism. But corporations lobbying for privileges (corporatism) is not the same
thing as whole industries collectively owning the means of production relevant
to their industry (corporativism). The two notions are distinct, and must be
treated separately.
Corporatism is not a system of social production.
Corporations lobby for privileges that hamper capitalism, it is true. But,
regardless of who instigates the hampering, hampered capitalism is capitalism
nonetheless.
And as Mises explained, corporativism is no more a
permanent social order than is interventionism.[9] The crux of the matter is the question of who is
to determine policy decisions within a given corporative: the landowners, the
capitalists, or the workers? If the state adjudicates between them, then it is
the state that is essentially disposing of the means of production, and thus
corporativism devolves into socialism. If the corporatives operate according to
a democratic principle, then it is the majority workers who will dictate
policy, and thus corporativism devolves into syndicalism.
Under syndicalism, the means of production of each
industry are owned by the workers of that industry. The syndicalist program is
distilled by the slogans "the railroads to the railroadmen!" and
"the mines to the miners!" Syndicalism too has been put forth as
another candidate, as a "third way" between capitalism and socialism.
But syndicalism is no system of social production either.[10] As soon as the needs of society change in the
slightest, how is a syndicalist order to adapt? Under capitalism, shifts in
consumer demand adjust prices. In seeking profits, entrepreneurs try to
anticipate these price adjustments, and thereby adjust the structure of
production to best satisfy consumer wants in the new state of affairs. In the
flux of the market, resources shift from one industry to another, in response
to consumer demand.
But, under syndicalism, why would any producer's
syndicate acquiesce to a diminution of its importance and wealth in society?
Production is for the sake of consumption, never the other way around.
Therefore, any system of social production worthy of the name must have some
means of at least conceivably adjusting production for the sake of consumption.
Even socialism ostensibly fits this bill, because the central administration at
least has the authority to adjust production by diktat in order to try to
better serve society (if not the intellectual means to do so rationally). But
no syndicalist has ever put forth any idea of how a syndicalist state would do
so that did not involve becoming, in essence, capitalism or socialism.
Thus, every economic policy decision is a two-pronged
fork in the road; there is no third prong. And neither are the two prongs
toward the "Left" and the "Right." There is capitalism, and
there is socialism.
One is tempted to say that the two prongs are
"forward" and "backward." This would be to adopt the
strategy of the Marxists who characterized everything they liked as
"progressive" (as well as everything they disliked as "reactionary").
But again, this would be eschewing scientific distinctions for political word
games. The honest man does not rely on catchwords and slogans in hopes that the
gullible public will latch onto his program by dint of its association with
words that resound favorably in their ears. The honest man tries to speak to
the mind of his listeners, not to their ears, because he is confident in the
inherent strength of his ideas. He will even accept unflattering names for his
position, and grant flattering names to his opponent's position, if that will
but put an end to the distracting word games and allow the true debate to
begin.
What is more "social" than the coordinated,
ecumenical society of mutual benefactors produced by capitalism? It is true
that capitalism progresses via the accumulation of capital. But the upshot of
increased capital in proportion to labor is an increase in the marginal
productivity of labor, and thus a rise in real wages. And if anything is
prejudicial to the vested interests of the already-rich capitalist, is it not
pure capitalism — which does not let him rest on his laurels but demands that
he never cease putting himself up to the test of the market, lest his fortune
gradually dwindle? Thus should not the market order be given a more flattering
(and descriptive) name than "capitalism"? Should not socialism, that
fundamentally antisocial program, be stigmatized with an ugly appellation?
Such are the distracting games of demagogues, and they
would only slow liberalism down. The most direct path to success is to use the
terms at hand, as they are found in the best literature in our tradition (which
happens to be the oeuvre of Ludwig von Mises), and simply explain what we mean
by them. Any sane person who learns what is truly entailed in "that which
is called capitalism" and what is truly entailed in "that which is
called socialism" will choose the former over the latter. That is because
socialism (which, again, is the only direction one can choose besides
capitalism) is social suicide. As Mises irrefutably proved as early as 1920,[11] the socialist state has no way of rationally
directing production. Socialism means discoordination, capital consumption,
famine, and death. Thus between capitalism and socialism (which, once more, are
the only two choices), the informed chooser could not have an easier choice to
make.
And this is the choice that is before everybody. The
fact that everybody in their right mind would choose capitalism, if only they
knew what the choice really meant, is why there is a harmony of interests.
Cognizance of this harmony of interests is what underpinned the scientific
liberalism (one might call it "harmonist" doctrine as Mises does[12]) that first arose in the writings of men like Hume,
Smith, and Condillac; that intellectually won the field in the days of Ricardo
and Say; and that had its greatest impact on policy in the days of Cobden and
Bastiat. And it was the denial of this harmony of interests — what amounted to
a philosophy of irreconcilable conflict (or, as Mises termed it, an
"anti-harmonist" doctrine) — that underpinned the revolt against
liberalism that reached its culmination in the 20th century.
This philosophy of irreconcilable conflict is yet
another common feature between the totalitarians of the so-called Left and
Right. With the overthrow of liberalism, the world once again came to embrace
the "Montaigne dogma": the incorrect notion that no group can gain
except by another group's loss.[13] This was the social philosophy of the
mercantalists, which was heroically overthrown by the early liberals. The
people of the early-20th-century West came under the sway of the new "anti-harmonism,"
dominant among the intellectuals of the time. Thus, adherence (or at least
acquiescence) to the party programs of the both the "far Right" and
"far Left" came naturally to them. They either adopted the Lebensraum doctrine of national conquest promoted
by the Nazis, Fascists, and other national imperialists, or the doctrine of
class warfare promoted by the internationalist Marxists. As Mises brilliantly
characterized it, the only important difference between the two doctrines was
that one divided society into irreconcilable camps vertically (along national
lines) and the other did the same horizontally (along class lines).[14]
The sooner classical liberals abandon the sloppy
distinctions of party politics and adopt the scientific distinctions of Ludwig
von Mises, the better will it be for our efforts in explaining to our fellow
human beings the stark choice that lies before them. Right vs. Left, fascist
vs. communist, all the alleged "middle ways" (interventionism,
syndicalism, corporativism, etc.) — these are all false choices. As Mises
demonstrated, ultimately there is one true dilemma in political economy. As he
wrote in Liberalism,
There is simply no other choice than this: either to abstain from interference in the free play of the market, or to delegate the entire management of production and distribution to the government. Either capitalism or socialism: there exists no middle way.
Notes
[5] Note that the autarkic household production of
primitive societies is not "social." And production for barter (which
Mises excludes from his definition of "market") is so necessarily ad hoc that it can never be part of a
"system."
[6] "If within a society based on private
ownership of the means of production some of these means are publicly owned and
operated, this still does not make for a mixed system which would combine
socialism and private property. As long as only certain individual enterprises
are publicly owned, the remaining being privately owned,the characteristics of the market economy which determine economic
activity remain essentially unimpaired." Mises, Interventionism: An Economic Analysis, "Introduction."
[8] "If the government is unwilling to
acquiesce in this undesired and undesirable outcome and goes further and
further … it eliminates the market altogether. Then the planned economy,
socialism of the GermanZwangswirtschaft pattern, is
substituted for the market economy. " Human Action, chapter 30, section 2.
No comments:
Post a Comment