by Robert Nozick
It is surprising that
intellectuals oppose free markets so. Other groups of comparable socio-economic
status do not show the same degree of opposition in the same proportions.
Statistically, then, intellectuals are an anomaly.
Not all intellectuals are on
the "left." Like other groups, their opinions are spread along a
curve. But in their case, the curve is shifted and skewed to the political
left.
By intellectuals, I do not
mean all people of intelligence or of a certain level of education, but those
who, in their vocation, deal with ideas as expressed in words, shaping the word
flow others receive. These wordsmiths include poets, novelists, literary
critics, newspaper and magazine journalists, and many professors. It does not
include those who primarily produce and transmit quantitatively or
mathematically formulated information (the numbersmiths) or those working in
visual media, painters, sculptors, cameramen. Unlike the wordsmiths, people in
these occupations do not disproportionately oppose free markets. The wordsmiths
are concentrated in certain occupational sites: academia, the media, government
bureaucracy.
Wordsmith intellectuals fare
well in capitalist society; there they have great freedom to formulate,
encounter, and propagate new ideas, to read and discuss them. Their
occupational skills are in demand, their income much above average. Why then do
they disproportionately oppose capitalism? Indeed, some data suggest that the
more prosperous and successful the intellectual, the more likely he is to
oppose capitalism. This opposition to capitalism is mainly "from the
left" but not solely so. Yeats, Eliot, and Pound opposed market society
from the right.
The opposition of wordsmith
intellectuals to capitalism is a fact of social significance. They shape our
ideas and images of society; they state the policy alternatives bureaucracies
consider. From treatises to slogans, they give us the sentences to express
ourselves. Their opposition matters, especially in a society that depends
increasingly upon the explicit formulation and dissemination of information.
We can distinguish two types
of explanation for the relatively high proportion of intellectuals in
opposition to capitalism. One type finds a factor unique to the anti-capitalist
intellectuals. The second type of explanation identifies a factor applying to
all intellectuals, a force propelling them toward anti-capitalist
views. Whether it pushes any particular intellectual over into anti-capitalism
will depend upon the other forces acting upon him. In the aggregate, though,
since it makes anti-capitalism more likely for each intellectual, such a factor
will produce a larger proportion of anti-capitalist intellectuals. Our
explanation will be of this second type. We will identify a factor which tilts
intellectuals toward anti-capitalist attitudes but does not guarantee it in any
particular case.
The Value of Intellectuals
Intellectuals now expect to be
the most highly valued people in a society, those with the most prestige and
power, those with the greatest rewards. Intellectuals feel entitled to
this. But, by and large, a capitalist society does not honor its intellectuals.
Ludwig von Mises explains the special resentment of intellectuals, in contrast
to workers, by saying they mix socially with successful capitalists and so have
them as a salient comparison group and are humiliated by their lesser status.
However, even those intellectuals who do not mix socially are similarly
resentful, while merely mixing is not enough--the sports and dancing
instructors who cater to the rich and have affairs with them are not noticeably
anti-capitalist.
Why then do contemporary intellectuals
feel entitled to the highest rewards their society has to
offer and resentful when they do not receive this?
Intellectuals feel they are the most valuable people, the ones with the highest
merit, and that society should reward people in accordance with their value and
merit. But a capitalist society does not satisfy the principle of distribution
"to each according to his merit or value." Apart from the gifts,
inheritances, and gambling winnings that occur in a free society, the market
distributes to those who satisfy the perceived market-expressed demands of
others, and how much it so distributes depends on how much is demanded and how
great the alternative supply is. Unsuccessful businessmen and workers do not
have the same animus against the capitalist system as do the wordsmith
intellectuals. Only the sense of unrecognized superiority, of entitlement
betrayed, produces that animus.
Why do wordsmith intellectuals
think they are most valuable, and why do they think distribution should be in
accordance with value? Note that this latter principle is not a necessary one.
Other distributional patterns have been proposed, including equal distribution,
distribution according to moral merit, distribution according to need. Indeed,
there need not be any pattern of distribution a society is aiming to achieve,
even a society concerned with justice. The justice of a distribution may reside
in its arising from a just process of voluntary exchange of justly acquired
property and services. Whatever outcome is produced by that process will be
just, but there is no particular pattern the outcome must fit. Why, then, do
wordsmiths view themselves as most valuable and accept the principle of
distribution in accordance with value?
From the beginnings of
recorded thought, intellectuals have told us their activity is most valuable.
Plato valued the rational faculty above courage and the appetites and deemed
that philosophers should rule; Aristotle held that intellectual contemplation
was the highest activity. It is not surprising that surviving texts record this
high evaluation of intellectual activity. The people who formulated
evaluations, who wrote them down with reasons to back them up, were
intellectuals, after all. They were praising themselves. Those who valued other
things more than thinking things through with words, whether hunting or power
or uninterrupted sensual pleasure, did not bother to leave enduring written
records. Only the intellectual worked out a theory of who was
best.
The Schooling of Intellectuals
What factor produced feelings
of superior value on the part of intellectuals? I want to focus on one
institution in particular: schools. As book knowledge became increasingly
important, schooling--the education together in classes of young people in reading
and book knowledge--spread. Schools became the major institution outside of the
family to shape the attitudes of young people, and almost all those who later
became intellectuals went through schools. There they were successful. They
were judged against others and deemed superior. They were praised and rewarded,
the teacher's favorites. How could they fail to see themselves as superior?
Daily, they experienced differences in facility with ideas, in
quick-wittedness. The schools told them, and showed them, they were better.
The schools, too, exhibited
and thereby taught the principle of reward in accordance with (intellectual)
merit. To the intellectually meritorious went the praise, the teacher's smiles,
and the highest grades. In the currency the schools had to offer, the smartest
constituted the upper class. Though not part of the official curricula, in the
schools the intellectuals learned the lessons of their own greater value in
comparison with the others, and of how this greater value entitled them to
greater rewards.
The wider market society,
however, taught a different lesson. There the greatest rewards did not go to
the verbally brightest. There the intellectual skills were not most highly
valued. Schooled in the lesson that they were most valuable, the most deserving
of reward, the most entitled to reward, how could the intellectuals, by and
large, fail to resent the capitalist society which deprived them of the just
deserts to which their superiority "entitled" them? Is it surprising
that what the schooled intellectuals felt for capitalist society was a deep and
sullen animus that, although clothed with various publicly appropriate reasons,
continued even when those particular reasons were shown to be inadequate?
In saying that intellectuals
feel entitled to the highest rewards the general society can offer (wealth,
status, etc.), I do not mean that intellectuals hold these rewards to be the
highest goods. Perhaps they value more the intrinsic rewards of intellectual
activity or the esteem of the ages. Nevertheless, they also feel entitled to
the highest appreciation from the general society, to the most and best it has
to offer, paltry though that may be. I don't mean to emphasize especially the
rewards that find their way into the intellectuals' pockets or even reach them
personally. Identifying themselves as intellectuals, they can resent the fact
that intellectual activity is not most highly valued and rewarded.
The intellectual wants the
whole society to be a school writ large, to be like the environment where he
did so well and was so well appreciated. By incorporating standards of reward
that are different from the wider society, the schools guarantee that some will
experience downward mobility later. Those at the top of the school's hierarchy will
feel entitled to a top position, not only in that micro-society but in the
wider one, a society whose system they will resent when it fails to treat them
according to their self-prescribed wants and entitlements. The school system
thereby produces anti-capitalist feeling among intellectuals. Rather, it
produces anti-capitalist feeling among verbal intellectuals. Why do the
numbersmiths not develop the same attitudes as these wordsmiths? I conjecture
that these quantitatively bright children, although they get good grades on the
relevant examinations, do not receive the same face-to-face attention and
approval from the teachers as do the verbally bright children. It is the verbal
skills that bring these personal rewards from the teacher, and apparently it is
these rewards that especially shape the sense of entitlement.
Central Planning in the
Classroom
There is a further point to be
added. The (future) wordsmith intellectuals are successful within the formal,
official social system of the schools, wherein the relevant rewards are
distributed by the central authority of the teacher. The schools contain
another informal social system within classrooms, hallways, and schoolyards,
wherein rewards are distributed not by central direction but spontaneously at
the pleasure and whim of schoolmates. Here the intellectuals do less well.
It is not surprising,
therefore, that distribution of goods and rewards via a centrally organized
distributional mechanism later strikes intellectuals as more appropriate than
the "anarchy and chaos" of the marketplace. For distribution in a
centrally planned socialist society stands to distribution in a capitalist
society as distribution by the teacher stands to distribution by the schoolyard
and hallway.
Our explanation does not
postulate that (future) intellectuals constitute a majority even of the
academic upper class of the school. This group may consist mostly of those with
substantial (but not overwhelming) bookish skills along with social grace,
strong motivation to please, friendliness, winning ways, and an ability to play
by (and to seem to be following) the rules. Such pupils, too, will be highly
regarded and rewarded by the teacher, and they will do extremely well in the
wider society, as well. (And do well within the informal social system of the
school. So they will not especially accept the norms of the school's formal
system.) Our explanation hypothesizes that (future) intellectuals are
disproportionately represented in that portion of the schools' (official) upper
class that will experience relative downward mobility. Or, rather, in the group
that predicts for itself a declining future. The animus will arise before the
move into the wider world and the experience of an actual decline in status, at
the point when the clever pupil realizes he (probably) will fare less well in
the wider society than in his current school situation. This unintended
consequence of the school system, the anti-capitalist animus of intellectuals,
is, of course, reinforced when pupils read or are taught by intellectuals who
present those very anti-capitalist attitudes.
No doubt, some wordsmith
intellectuals were cantankerous and questioning pupils and so were disapproved
of by their teachers. Did they too learn the lesson that the best should get
the highest rewards and think, despite their teachers, that they themselves
were best and so start with an early resentment against the school system's
distribution? Clearly, on this and the other issues discussed here, we need
data on the school experiences of future wordsmith intellectuals to refine and
test our hypotheses.
Stated as a general point, it
is hardly contestable that the norms within schools will affect the normative
beliefs of people after they leave the schools. The schools, after all, are the
major non-familial society that children learn to operate in, and hence
schooling constitutes their preparation for the larger non-familial society. It
is not surprising that those successful by the norms of a school system should
resent a society, adhering to different norms, which does not grant them the
same success. Nor, when those are the very ones who go on to shape a society's
self-image, its evaluation of itself, is it surprising when the society's
verbally responsive portion turns against it. If you were designing a society,
you would not seek to design it so that the wordsmiths, with all their
influence, were schooled into animus against the norms of the society.
Our explanation of the
disproportionate anti-capitalism of intellectuals is based upon a very
plausible sociological generalization.
In a society where one
extra-familial system or institution, the first young people enter, distributes
rewards, those who do the very best therein will tend to internalize the norms
of this institution and expect the wider society to operate in accordance with
these norms; they will feel entitled to distributive shares in accordance with
these norms or (at least) to a relative position equal to the one these norms
would yield. Moreover, those constituting the upper class within the hierarchy
of this first extra-familial institution who then experience (or foresee
experiencing) movement to a lower relative position in the wider society will,
because of their feeling of frustrated entitlement, tend to oppose the wider
social system and feel animus toward its norms.
Notice that this is not a
deterministic law. Not all those who experience downward social mobility will
turn against the system. Such downward mobility, though, is a factor which
tends to produce effects in that direction, and so will show itself in
differing proportions at the aggregate level. We might distinguish ways an
upper class can move down: it can get less than another group or (while no
group moves above it) it can tie, failing to get more than those previously
deemed lower. It is the first type of downward mobility which especially
rankles and outrages; the second type is far more tolerable. Many intellectuals
(say they) favor equality while only a small number call for an aristocracy of
intellectuals. Our hypothesis speaks of the first type of downward mobility as
especially productive of resentment and animus.
The school system imparts and
rewards only some skills relevant to later success (it is,
after all, a specialized institution) so its reward system will differ from
that of the wider society. This guarantees that some, in moving to the wider
society, will experience downward social mobility and its attendant
consequences. Earlier I said that intellectuals want the society to be the
schools writ large. Now we see that the resentment due to a frustrated sense of
entitlement stems from the fact that the schools (as a specialized first
extra-familial social system) are not the society writ small.
Our explanation now seems to
predict the (disproportionate) resentment of schooled
intellectuals against their society whatever its nature, whether capitalist or
communist. (Intellectuals are disproportionately opposed to capitalism as
compared with other groups of similar socioeconomic status within capitalist
society. It is another question whether they are disproportionately opposed as
compared with the degree of opposition of intellectuals in other societies to
those societies.) Clearly, then, data about the attitudes of intellectuals
within communist countries toward apparatchiks would be relevant; will those
intellectuals feel animus toward that system?
Our hypothesis needs to be
refined so that it does not apply (or apply as strongly) to every society. Must
the school systems in every society inevitably produce anti-societal animus in
the intellectuals who do not receive that society's highest rewards? Probably
not. A capitalist society is peculiar in that it seems to announce that it is
open and responsive only to talent, individual initiative, personal merit.
Growing up in an inherited caste or feudal society creates no expectation that
reward will or should be in accordance with personal value. Despite the created
expectation, a capitalist society rewards people only insofar as they serve the
market-expressed desires of others; it rewards in accordance with economic
contribution, not in accordance with personal value. However, it comes close
enough to rewarding in accordance with value--value and contribution will very
often be intermingled--so as to nurture the expectation produced by the
schools. The ethos of the wider society is close enough to that of the schools
so that the nearness creates resentment. Capitalist societies reward individual
accomplishment or announce they do, and so they leave the intellectual, who
considers himself most accomplished, particularly bitter.
Another factor, I think, plays
a role. Schools will tend to produce such anti-capitalist attitudes the more
they are attended together by a diversity of people. When almost all of those
who will be economically successful are attending separate schools, the
intellectuals will not have acquired that attitude of being superior to
them. But even if many children of the upper class attend separate
schools, an open society will have other schools that also include many who
will become economically successful as entrepreneurs, and the intellectuals
later will resentfully remember how superior they were academically to their
peers who advanced more richly and powerfully. The openness of the society has
another consequence, as well. The pupils, future wordsmiths and others, will
not know how they will fare in the future. They can hope for anything. A
society closed to advancement destroys those hopes early. In an open capitalist
society, the pupils are not resigned early to limits on their advancement and
social mobility, the society seems to announce that the most capable and
valuable will rise to the very top, their schools have already given the
academically most gifted the message that they are most valuable and deserving
of the greatest rewards, and later these very pupils with the highest
encouragement and hopes see others of their peers, whom they know and saw to be
less meritorious, rising higher than they themselves, taking the foremost
rewards to which they themselves felt themselves entitled. Is it any wonder
they bear that society an animus?
Some Further Hypotheses
We have refined the hypothesis
somewhat. It is not simply formal schools but formal schooling in a specified
social context that produces anti-capitalist animus in (wordsmith)
intellectuals. No doubt, the hypothesis requires further refining. But enough.
It is time to turn the hypothesis over to the social scientists, to take it
from armchair speculations in the study and give it to those who will immerse
themselves in more particular facts and data. We can point, however, to some
areas where our hypothesis might yield testable consequences and predictions.
First, one might predict that the more meritocratic a country's school system,
the more likely its intellectuals are to be on the left. (Consider France.)
Second, those intellectuals who were "late bloomers" in school would
not have developed the same sense of entitlement to the very highest rewards;
therefore, a lower percentage of the late-bloomer intellectuals will be
anti-capitalist than of the early bloomers. Third, we limited our hypothesis to
those societies (unlike Indian caste society) where the successful student
plausibly could expect further comparable success in the wider society. In
Western society, women have not heretofore plausibly held such expectations, so
we would not expect the female students who constituted part of the academic
upper class yet later underwent downward mobility to show the same anti-capitalist
animus as male intellectuals. We might predict, then, that the more a society
is known to move toward equality in occupational opportunity between women and
men, the more its female intellectuals will exhibit the same disproportionate
anti-capitalism its male intellectuals show.
Some readers may doubt this
explanation of the anti-capitalism of intellectuals. Be this as it may, I think
that an important phenomenon has been identified. The sociological
generalization we have stated is intuitively compelling; something like it must
be true. Some important effect therefore must be produced in that portion of
the school's upper class that experiences downward social mobility, some
antagonism to the wider society must get generated. If that effect is not the
disproportionate opposition of the intellectuals, then what is it? We started
with a puzzling phenomenon in need of an explanation. We have found, I think,
an explanatory factor that (once stated) is so obvious that we must believe it
explains some real phenomenon.
No comments:
Post a Comment