When I was a small boy adults used to say to me, ‘If you ask a silly question
you’ll get a silly answer.’ This irritated my nascent sense of logic: for if I
genuinely did not know the answer to my question, how could I possibly be
expected to know that it was silly? And could anything be silly in the absence
of knowledge that it was? This was my childish equivalent of Socrates’ or
Plato’s doctrine that no one does wrong willingly: a doctrine that does not
accord with my clinical experience as a doctor, let alone with my experience of
life. But at the time, the accusation of silliness seemed to me worse than
merely wrong: it was unjust. I did not appreciate at that age that there could
be such a thing as a responsibility to know, even if one did not.
One of silliest
questions I have ever heard, and heard often, is why some or many countries are
poor. This is to get everything exactly the wrong way round, as if Man were
born rich and had somehow to achieve poverty. Of course, it is possible for
those who were formerly rich to become poor, for example by improvidence or the
spoliation of others; but immemorial poverty requires no explanation. It is
wealth that needs explaining, mankind not having been born in marble halls with
a silver spoon in its mouth.
I once bought a
slender volume entitled Why Bad Dogs? This set out to explain
why some dogs barked incessantly, bit the postman, wouldn’t walk to heel and so
forth. I am such a dog-lover that I find it difficult to put myself in the
place of those who dislike dogs, but still I wondered whether the question
asked by the title was the correct one. Dog-lover as I am, I am not the
Rousseau of dogs; I do not think that canine nature, untouched by association
with humans, is good; and if I were writing the Social Contract for
Dogs, I should not begin ‘Dogs are born good, but everywhere they
bark.’
Clearly it is
important to frame one’s questions correctly if one wants a real answer: often
one does not, for the interrogative is not always used simply to obtain
information but also to confound and irritate, as every child knows. The other
day I came across a book published in 1937 by A R Powys, one of the Powys family
that produced so many writers, mostly unread today, though some were well-known
in their day and John Cowper Powys still has his devotees. His brother, A R
Powys (1882 – 1936), was an architect and preserver of ancient buildings who
also wrote essays on architecture, and one of them in the book that I came
across, From the Ground Up, was titled Origins of Bad
Architecture. This is a question that has long troubled me, so much so that
my wife says I have become something of a bore on it. Whenever I see an eyesore
in otherwise beautiful surroundings, which is often, I remark upon it,
whereupon my wife, who agrees that the twentieth century was an urban aesthetic
disaster, tells me I should clam down (eyesores make me angry) because what is
done is done, and working myself up about it will do the landscape no good and
will do me harm.
But is the origin
of bad architecture the right question to ask, as if it were in the nature of
architecture to be good unless some disturbing factor intervened? First,
however, I cannot forebear from remarking on the frontispiece of the book, a
photo of the author. He is a most distinguished-looking man, of a kind that one
does not, or at any rate that I do not, see today. If the face is the window of
the soul, then this man was aesthetically fastidious, sensitive, inquiring,
honest, upright and truthful, a man whom one would feel it peculiarly disgraceful
to deceive in even the smallest matters. One cannot imagine him for a moment
writing what he did not believe to be true (and therefore he was not a true
modern intellectual) or telling a lie. That he was a man of exceptional probity
is confirmed in the introduction to the volume written by his most famous
brother, John Cowper Powys, admittedly not an entirely unbiased source:
Nothing in his life was at random. Nothing was wanton or wilful. In dress, in ablution, in food, in drink, in the minutest arrangements of his time, of the objects around him, of his rooms, of his garden, of his household utensils, in lighting a fire, in opening a bottle, in whittling a stick, in driving a nail, in hanging a picture, in washing a dish, in chopping a log, in cutting a loaf, he would always follow a carefully considered method of his own, for which when challenged… he would bring forth a most confounding and irrefutable weight of elaborate justification.
Such integrity in
everything that he did is perhaps slightly intimidating to us lesser mortals
who have it not, but it nevertheless has the enormous merit of not taking
anything in life for granted, in paying close attention to every small thing,
of finding purpose everywhere, and therefore of avoiding the blight of modern
life, namely meaninglessness and boredom. These are much underestimated factors
in the promotion of social pathology in our societies, and explain the
restless, constant and self-defeating search for entertainment or distraction,
or that for all-encompassing ideologies or self-absorbing causes among people
of rather more intellectual disposition. The integrity of A R Powys, I say, is
inscribed on his face, though here I must add a small caveat: physiognomy is
not an exact science, though we all practise it, and when I first saw a picture
of Mr Madoff, him of the century and a half prison sentence, I confess that I
saw in him just the kind of calm, thoughtful and honest man to whom I should
have liked to entrust my money, such as it is.
The integrity of A
R Powys notwithstanding, is the question he asks, that of what makes for bad
architecture, the right one? Should we not rather be asking, ‘What is good
architecture?’ and then, when we have decided this question, examine in what
ways bad architecture habitually departs from the answer we have given?
This Powys
specifically denies. Indeed, it is his position that theorising about the
principles of good architecture, especially when it is believed that they have
been found, is one of the sources of bad architecture. I am not sure he is
absolutely right in this: Palladio, Vitruvius and Alberti all theorised about
architecture, not without a certain practical success. But they were a long
time ago, and the theorists of his time were a lot less trustworthy: they had a
deeply destructive impulse or instinct, perhaps strengthened by or even
originating in the catastrophe that was the First World War. If that –
the war – is what our civilisation wrought, it is time for something completely
new and different.
The problem of bad
architecture is more acute in Europe than anywhere else in the world, in large
part because Europe has such an immemorial tradition of great and, more to the
point, good vernacular architecture. The aesthetically bad is much more painful
to behold in proximity to the good than it is when everything around it is bad.
Then it is like a wound to the eye. That is why, if anyone wants to study bad
architecture, he should go to Paris.
A strange choice,
you say! Is not Paris the City of Light? Is it not the most beautiful city in
the world, with the possible exception of Venice? Quite so: that is why it is
so essential to study what has been built there in the second half of the
twentieth century, for there is no modern architecture in the world worse than
French. Go to the Tour Montparnasse, thou architect, consider its ways and be
wise (or to the Centre Pompidou or Musée du Quai Branly, for that
matter).
It is true,
perhaps, that modern architecture in France has passed its nadir (one certainly
hopes so, for no nadir was, if I may be allowed a neologism, nadirer than the
French), but even now it cannot rise above a glassy, saurian, impersonal
elegance indistinguishable from the same kind of building in Manila or
Santiago, and towards which it is, and will always be, impossible to feel any
individual affection or warmth. This architecture is for the cold-blooded, for
‘communication’ rather than for speech.
I have asked
architects and architectural historians why it is that we in Europe are
incapable of building a single charming house, let alone an entire urban
environment that is other than a visual nightmare. The answers they have given
are various (none has dared deny the premise of the question).
They say that we
cannot use the methods, materials or designs of the past. This seems to me
inexact. I can quite see that, for economic and social reasons, it is
impossible to use the methods and perhaps the materials of the past. A
bricklayer or stonemason now commands too high a wage for his manual labour to
make it possible for houses or other buildings to be built on any scale in the
old fashion. The bricklayer or mason himself expects to live at a standard of
living not so very different from that of the person for whom he is building.
But design, at
least in Europe, is another question altogether. There is actually no reason at
all why old designs cannot be reproduced, albeit with mass-produced materials.
Indeed, in London recently a housing authority did precisely this; it copied
precisely the elegant early Victorian buildings (still of Regency inspiration)
of three sides of a residential square in restoring the fourth side. It did not
use Victorian methods, but it used Victorian designs, with triumphant result,
far, far better than any residential architecture of the recent past.
Why was this
expedient never thought of before? Why instead was so much ugliness – and
ugliness on a new and inhuman scale – constructed not merely faute de
mieux or as a necessary evil in the unfortunate circumstances, but
with the proud ideological rodomontade of the entire architectural profession,
a rodomontade in which even now it has not ceased to indulge? (No profession
likes to face up to its crimes, of course.)
The reason, I
suspect, is not merely economic, for even where no expense is spared the result
is usually catastrophic. The reason is much deeper.
Modern man’s
religion is progress: what comes later must be better than what went before.
And there are clearly whole fields of human endeavour in which this is so. No
one, I suppose, would wish to be operated upon by surgeons using the methods of
1830. (Even in medicine, however, it is sometimes worth remembering that the
very latest is not necessarily the very best, and the supposition that it is
has occasionally led to disaster.)
But aesthetics are
not science: aesthetics do not show the same inbuilt tendency to improvement.
From the aesthetic point of view what comes after is not necessarily better
than what went before, and is often worse, even much worse. Particularly in an
age of progress, however, men are reluctant to admit that they cannot do better
than their forebears; to admit it is to admit the heresy that beauty’s arrow,
unlike that of time, does not fly in one direction only. A return to the
pattern or design of the past – dismissed as pastiche, the worst of
all architectural crimes, far worse than destroying an immemorial townscape –
would indicate a deficiency of imagination, inventiveness and originality, all
the qualities that make the artist, at least in the romantic
conception of the artist. And architects, in their own conception, are above
all artists: artists, moreover, when it is widely believed that the
purpose of art is to challenge, to question, to transgress, never to celebrate,
to harmonise, to console, to give meaning.
How different from
the spirit of A R Powys, of whom his brother writes:
The bulk of his life’s work lies where he would have had it lie, in the silent and unapplauding masonry and timber of the irreplaceable buildings he saved from ruin…
He draws attention
to his ‘self-effacement,’ a characteristic that architects today – like almost
everyone else – rejects as treason to the self.
Le Corbusier,
writing of the years pre-dating the First World War, said that there was no
architecture of the time, that architecture was dead. He used this as a pretext
and justification for his own purely destructive and megalomaniac impulses. But
what he said was simply not true, as the most casual inspection of Paris will
inform anyone with eyes to see.
Recently I stayed
in Paris for three weeks, in an apartment block built in 1905, precisely the
time of which Le Corbusier wrote so contemptuously. It was in an arrondissement
that was once unfashionable but has since gone up in the world, in no small
part thanks to apartment blocks such as the one in which I stayed. My block was
elegant and obviously owed something to art nouveau; it was not
great architecture in the way that the Parthenon or the Taj Mahal are great
architecture, but it was highly civilised, pleasing to the eye, functional and
helped to create one of the most agreeable urban environments the world has
known. Needless to say, it was in keeping with what already existed around it.
The reward of the
architect, now otherwise completely forgotten, was his name, carved in small
letters, on stone facing, together with that of the builder: the same as on
other, equally elegant and agreeable apartment blocks. He understood, as
so many architects today do not seem or want to understand, that egotism is a
deadly sin in architects, the deadliest in fact, and that A R Powys’ happy
mixture of pride and modesty was very necessary. And the pride must be in the
work, not the person.
No comments:
Post a Comment