In the name of education, welfare, taxation, safety, health, the environment, and other laudable ends, the new despotism confronts us at every turn
"The greatest single revolution of the last century in the political sphere has been the transfer of effective power over human lives from the constitutionally visible offices of government, the nominally sovereign offices, to the vast network that has been brought into being in the name of protection of the people from their exploiters"
by Robert A. Nisbet
When the modern
political community was being shaped at the end of the 18th century, its
founders thought that the consequences of republican or representative
institutions in government would be the reduction of political power in individual
lives.
Nothing seems to
have mattered more to such minds as Montesquieu, Turgot, and Burke in Europe
and to Adams, Jefferson, and Franklin in the United States than the expansion
of freedom in the day-to-day existence of human beings, irrespective of class,
occupation, or belief.
Hence the
elaborate, carefully contrived provisions of constitution or law whereby formal
government would be checked, limited, and given root in the smallest possible
assemblies of the people.
The kind of
arbitrary power Burke so detested and referred to almost constantly in his
attacks upon the British government in its relation to the American colonists
and the people of India and Ireland, and upon the French government during the
revolution, was foremost in the minds of all the architects of the political
community, and they thought it could be eliminated, or reduced to
insignificance, by ample use of legislative and judicial machinery.
What we have
witnessed, however, in every Western country, and not least in the United States,
is the almost incessant growth in power over the lives of human beings – power
that is basically the result of the gradual disappearance of all the
intermediate institutions which, coming from the predemocratic past, served for
a long time to check the kind of authority that almost from the beginning
sprang from the new legislative bodies and executives in the modern
democracies.
The 18th-century
hope that people, by their direct participation in government, through voting
and office holding, would be correspondingly loath to see political power grow,
has been proved wrong. Nothing seems so calculated to expand and intensify the power
of the state as the expansion of electorates and the general popularization of
the uses of power.
Even so, I do not
think we can properly explain the immense power that exists in modern
democracies by reference solely to the enlargement of the base of government or
to the kinds of parliaments Sir Henry Maine warned against in his Popular Government. Had political
power remained visible, as it largely did down until about World
War I, and the manifest function of legislature and executive, the matter would
be very different.
What has in fact
happened during the past half century is that the bulk of power in our society,
as it affects our intellectual, economic, social, and cultural existences, has
become largely invisible, a function of the vast infragovernment
composed of bureaucracy's commissions, agencies, and departments in a myriad of
areas. And the reason this power is so commonly invisible to the eye is that it
lies concealed under the humane purposes that have brought it into existence.
The greatest
single revolution of the last century in the political sphere has been the
transfer of effective power over human lives from the constitutionally visible
offices of government, the nominally sovereign offices, to the vast network
that has been brought into being in the name of protection of the people from
their exploiters.
It is this kind of
power that Justice Brandeis warned against in a decision nearly half a century
ago.
Experience should
teach us to be most on guard to protect liberty when the governments' purposes
are beneficent. Men born to freedom are naturally alert to repel invasion of
their liberty by evil-minded rulers. The greatest dangers to liberty lurk in
insidious encroachments by men of zeal, well-meaning but without understanding.
What gives the new
despotism its peculiar effectiveness is indeed its liaison with
humanitarianism, but beyond this fact is its capacity for entering into the
smallest details of human life.
The most absolute
authority, wrote Rousseau,
is that which penetrates into a man's inmost being and concerns itself no less with his will than with his actions.
The truth of that
observation is in no way lessened by the fact that for Rousseau genuinely
legitimate government, government based upon the general will, should so
penetrate. Rousseau saw correctly that the kind of power traditionally
exercised by kings and princes, represented chiefly by the tax collector and
the military, was in fact a very weak kind of power compared with what a
philosophy of government resting on the general will could bring about.
Tocqueville, from
a vastly different philosophy of the state, also took note of the kind of power
Rousseau described.
It must not be
forgotten that it is especially dangerous to enslave men in the minor details
of life. For my part, I should be inclined to think freedom less necessary in
the great things than in the little ones, if it were possible to be secure of
the one without the other.
Congresses and
legislatures pass laws, executives enforce them, and the courts interpret them.
These, as I have said, are the bodies on which the attentions of the Founding
Fathers were fixed. They are the visible organs of government to this day, the
objects of constant reporting in the media. And I would not question the
capacity of each of them to interfere substantially with individual freedom.
But of far greater
importance in the realm of freedom is that invisible government created in the
first instance by legislature and executive but rendered in due time largely
autonomous, is often nearly impervious to the will of elected constitutional
bodies. In ways too numerous even to try to list, the invisible government –
composed of commissions, bureaus, and regulatory agencies of every imaginable
kind – enters daily into what Tocqueville calls "the minor details of
life."
Murray Weidenbaum,
in an important study of this invisible government, Government Mandated Price Increases, has correctly
referred to "a second managerial revolution" that is now well under
way in American society. The first managerial revolution, described originally
by A.A. Berle and Gardiner C. Means in their classic book The Modern Corporation and Private Property and given
explicit identity by James Burnham, concerned, as Weidenbaum points out, the
separation of management from formal ownership in the modern corporation.
The second
managerial revolution is very different. "This time," writes
Weidenbaum,
the shift is from the professional management selected by the corporation's board of directors to the vast cadre of government regulators that influences and often controls the key decisions of the typical business firm
Weidenbaum
concerns himself almost entirely with the business sector – pointing out
incidentally that this whole cadre of regulation is a by now deeply embedded
cause of inflation – but the point he makes is just as applicable to other,
non business areas of society.
In the name of
education, welfare, taxation, safety, health, the environment, and other
laudable ends, the new despotism confronts us at every turn. Its effectiveness
lies, as I say, in part through liaison with humanitarian rather than nakedly
exploitative objectives but also, and perhaps most significantly, in its
capacity to deal with the human will rather than with mere human actions.
"The kind of power traditionally exercised by kings and princes, represented chiefly by the tax collector and the military, was in fact a very weak kind of power compared with what a philosophy of government resting on the general will could bring about."
By the very
existence of one or another of the regulatory offices of the invisible
government that now occupies foremost place, the wills of educators,
researchers, artists, philanthropists, and enterprisers in all areas, as well
as in business, are bound to be affected: to be shaped, bent, driven, even
extinguished.
Of all the social
or moral objectives, however, which are the taking-off points of the new
despotism in our times, there is one that stands out clearly, that has widest
possible appeal, and that at the present time undoubtedly represents the
greatest single threat to liberty and social initiative. I refer to equality,
or, more accurately, to the New Equality.
The foremost, or
indeed the sole, condition required in order to succeed in centralizing the
supreme power in a democratic community is to love equality or to get men to
believe you love it. Thus, the science of despotism, which was once so complex,
has been simplified and reduced, as it were, to a single principle.
The words are
Tocqueville's, toward the end of Democracy in America, in partial
summary of the central thesis of that book, which is the affinity between
centralization of power and mass equalitarianism. Tocqueville yielded to no one
in his appreciation of equality before the law. It was, he thought, vital to a
creative society and a free state.
It was
Tocqueville's genius, however, to see the large possibility of the growth in
the national state of another kind of equality, more akin to the kind of
leveling that war and centralization bring to a social order. It is only in our
time that his words have become analytic and descriptive rather than prophetic.
There is a great
deal in common between military collectivism and the kind of society that must
be the certain result of the doctrines of the New Equalitarians, whose aim is
not mere increase in equality before the law.
In fact this
historic type of equality looms as an obstacle to the kind of equality that is
desired: equality of condition, equality of result.
There is nothing paradoxical in the fondness of equalitarians for centralized
power, the kind that the military best evidences, and the fondness of
centralizers for equality. The latter, whatever else it may signify, means the
absence of the kinds of centers of authority and rank that are always dangerous
to despotic governments.
Equality of
condition or result is one thing when it is set in the utopian community, the
commune, or the monastery. The Benedictine Rule is as good a guide as we need
for the administration of this kind of equalitarian order, small enough,
personal enough to prevent the dogma of equality from extinguishing normal
diversity of strength and talent.
For countless
centuries, everywhere in the world, religion and kinship have been contexts of
this kind of equality; they still are in theme.
Equality of result
is a very different thing, however, when it becomes the guiding policy of the
kind of national state that exists in the West today – founded in war and
bureaucracy, its power strengthened by these forces throughout modern history,
and dependent from the beginning upon a degree of leveling of the population.
We may have in
mind the ideal of equality that the monastery or family represents, but what we
will get in actual fact in the modern state is the kind of equality that goes
with uniformity and homogeneity – above all, with war society.
Tocqueville was by
no means alone in his perception of the affinity between equality and power. At
the very end of the 18th century, Edmund Burke had written, in Reflections on the Revolution in France, of the passion
for leveling that exists in the militant and the military: those, he wrote,
"who attempt to level, never equalize."
"Socialists such as Jaures in France saw in the citizen army, based upon universal conscription, an admirable means of instilling in Frenchmen greater love for equality than for the liberty associated with capitalist society."
The French
Revolution, Burke believed correctly, was different from any revolution that
had ever taken place before. And the reason for this difference lay in its
combination of eradication of social diversity on the one hand and, on the
other, the relentless increase of military-political power that expressed
itself in the timeworn fashion of such power.
All that tended
toward the destruction of the intermediate authorities of social class,
province, church, and family brought simultaneously into being, Burke noted, a
social leveling and a transfer to the state alone of powers previously resident
in a plurality of associations.
"Everything depends upon the army in such a government as yours," he wrote; "for you have industriously destroyed all the opinions and prejudices, and, as far as in you lay, all the instincts which support government."
In words prophetic
indeed, since they were written in 1790, Burke further declared that the crisis
inherent in "military democracy" could only be resolved by the rise
of "some popular general who understands the art of conciliating the
soldiery, and who possesses the true spirit of command." Such an
individual' "shall draw the eyes of all men upon himself."
The theme of
military democracy, of the union of military and social equality, was strong in
certain 19th-century critics. We see it in some of Burckhardt's writings, where
he refers to the future rise of "military commandos" in circumstances
of rampant equality.
We see it, perhaps
most profoundly, in James Fitzjames Stephen's Liberty, Equality, and Fraternity, though what is
most evident in that remarkable work is much less the military, save by
implication, than the implacable conflict Stephen discerned between equality
and liberty.
There were others
– Henry Adams in America, Taine in France, Nietzsche in Germany – who called
attention to the problem equality creates for liberty in the modern democratic
state. Nor were such perceptions confined to the pessimists.
Socialists such as
Jaures in France saw in the citizen army, based upon universal conscription, an
admirable means of instilling in Frenchmen greater love for equality than for
the liberty associated with capitalist society.
It is evident in
our day how much more of a force the ethic of equality has become since these
19th-century prophecies and prescriptions were uttered. Two world wars and a
major depression have advanced bureaucracy and its inherent regimentations to a
point where the ideology of equality becomes more and more a means of
rationalizing these regimentations and less and less a force serving individual
life or liberty.
No comments:
Post a Comment