by Frank Furedi
In virtually every Western society, education is in trouble.
In part, the
crisis of schooling is a product of the politicisation of education. In recent
decades, education has been transformed into an instrument of public policy, a
means for achieving objectives that are entirely external to learning.
Education is now expected to put right the failures of adult society, to
transform apathetic youngsters into responsible citizens. Education is meant to
promote social mobility, multiculturalism, responsible sex, sound financial
behaviour and emotional wellbeing, and to provide youngsters with a variety of
key skills.
The instrumental
transformation of education into a vehicle for achieving policy objectives
means that it is rarely appreciated as something valuable in its own right.
Education has been so instrumentalised that its main function is now to
‘provide skills’. The teaching of knowledge itself, for its own sake, is
frequently dismissed as an old-fashioned custom that is not relevant to the
twenty-first century.
That policymakers
confuse education with training is regrettable, but understandable. Far more
worrying is the fact that a significant section of the teaching profession has
also embraced the philistine skills agenda. Indeed, Britain’s education
establishment is if anything more ideologically devoted to
instrumental pedagogy than is the Lib-Con coalition government. This became
painfully clear at the recent conferences of English teachers’ unions, where
opposition to the government was often expressed through denunciations of
knowledge-based curricula.
So we heard Alex
Kenny, a member of the executive of the National Union of Teachers, dismiss the
government’s new national curriculum on the grounds that it is ‘high on content
and low on skills’. Numerous delegates attacked the curriculum’s emphasis on
core knowledge. A survey of 2,000 NUT members revealed that two
thirds of teachers are hostile to the government’s plans to place less emphasis
on skills.
This means we have
a paradoxical situation, where politicians seem to take the teaching of subject-based
knowledge more seriously than educators do. The philistine attitude towards
education adopted by some NUT delegates was exposed most strikingly through
their confusion of knowledge with facts. Kenny, for instance, said a
knowledge-based curriculum is one ‘based on pub quiz-style chinks of
information’. The NUT’s general secretary, Christine Blower, equated the
acquisition of knowledge with rote learning and said ‘it doesn’t promote the critical
thinking and problem-solving skills that are essential for good quality
learning’. Her words reflect the current wisdom of utilitarian pedagogy:
learning and skills are better than education.
Knowledge and skills
In any discussion
about the relationship between analytical skills and knowledge, it is easy to
become one-sided. Often, too much of a polarising distinction is made between
knowledge and its application. It is possible to make a distinction: knowledge
is accomplished through learning principles, concepts and facts, while skills
represent the capacity to use that knowledge in specific contexts. But in
reality, these two things are inextricably bound together. The gaining of
knowledge, particularly deep knowledge, requires such skills as the capacity to
conceptualise, compare and critically engage.
Education
unleashes a dynamic process in which a greater depth of knowledge can be
achieved through application – that is, through using the power of abstraction
or experiment. Through the greater acquisition of knowledge, one becomes more
sensitive to, and better at, applying it. Contrary to the NUT executive’s
prioritisation of skills provision, it is knowledge that provides children with
the capacity to conceptualise, compare and abstract. Knowledge is logically
prior to analytical skills. The logical priority of knowledge does not mean
skills are unimportant, or even less important. It simply means that
disciplinary knowledge provides the intellectual and cultural foundation for
the exercise of what Aristotle called phronesis: the virtue of
practical thought.
Critics of the
‘knowledge model’ of education are often really calling into question the
authority of knowledge itself. The pedagogic devaluation of a knowledge-based
curriculum is fuelled by a powerful anti-intellectual ethos that refuses to
take ideas seriously. From this philistine perspective, knowledge is reducible
to facts and information. Accordingly, acquiring knowledge is seen as being
akin to memorising facts. Hence the misleading depiction of knowledge
acquisition as a form of ‘rote learning’.
One recurring
argument against knowledge-led curricula is that they quickly become outdated
in our ever-changing world. Mary Bousted, general secretary of the Association
of Teachers and Lecturers, says that since ‘what is known to be true changes by
the hour’, the ‘rote learning of facts must give way to nurturing through
education of essential transferable skills’ (1). ‘Truth’ is depicted as a
momentary epiphenomenon, and knowledge acquisition is caricatured as the ‘rote
learning of facts’.
The view of truth
and knowledge as unstable, transitory things is now widespread among opponents
to rigorous, academic-based school curricula. The position statement of one
teachers’ union asserts that ‘a
twenty-first-century curriculum cannot have the transfer of knowledge at its
core for the simple reason that the selection of what is required has become
problematic in an information-rich age’. Once again, critics fail to
distingiuish between knowledge and information. It is society’s knowledge that
gives meaning to new information, through allowing people to
interpret new facts and helping society to understand what significance or
otherwise should be attached to such facts. Far from allowing the so-called
‘information age’ to undermine knowledge, we should trust knowledge, treated
and transmitted seriously, to help people negotiate information highways.
Through
appropriating new experiences and ideas, knowledge itself develops. But the
‘latest knowledge’ is always organically linked to that which preceded it.
Today’s scepticism towards the authority of knowledge implicitly calls into
question the meaning of education itself. Once the knowledge of the past is
rendered obsolescent, what can education mean? If ‘what is known to be true
changes by the hour’, what is there left to teach?
Educationalists
often talk about ‘breaks’ and ‘ruptures’, claiming that nothing is as it was
and that the present has been decoupled from the past. Their worldview is
shaped by great short-termism, by a feeling of being so overwhelmed by the
displacement of the old by the new that they forget that historical experience
may actually continue to be relevant to our lives. Discussions about the
relationship between education and change are frequently overwhelmed by fads
and by the superficial symptoms of new developments. This overlooks the fact
that the fundamental educational needs of students do not alter every time a
new technology is invented. Certainly the questions raised by Greek philosophy,
Renaissance poetry, Enlightenment science or the novels of George Eliot
continue to be relevant for students in this age, just as they were to students
who lived and studied long before the dawning of the Digital Age.
Knowledge is not
simply the sum total of a body of facts; it is based on concepts, theories and
specific structures of thought. So even if some of the content of knowledge
changes in line with new developments, its structure and concepts can retain
their significance for very long periods of time. Geometric theorems may be
contested over time, but they nonetheless express a body of knowledge that
transcends centuries.
Understanding change
The fetishisation
of change, the obsession with ‘rupture’, speaks to today’s intellectual
malaise, in which truth, knowledge and meaning are treated as provisional and
arbitrary things. Perversely, the transformation of change into a metaphysical
force haunting humanity actually weakens society’s ability to distinguish
between a passing novelty and a qualitative change. That is why lessons learned
through the experiences and knowledge of the past are so important for helping
society face the future. When change is objectified, it turns into a spectacle,
something we observe rather than affect; we become cavalier about the truths
and insights that emerged from and through the greatest moments in human
history. Yet these truths came from attempts to find answers to many of the
deepest, most durable questions facing humanity, and the more the world
changes, the more we need to draw on our cultural and intellectual inheritance
from the past.
If the legacy of
the past ceases to have relevance to the schooling of young people, what can
education mean? Historically, serious thinkers from across the left-right
divide recognised that education is a transaction between generations. Antonio
Gramsci, the Italian Marxist, wrote that ‘in reality each generation educates
the new generation’. From a conservative perspective, the English philosopher
Michael Oakeshott said ‘education in its most general significance may be
recognised as a specific transaction which may go on between the generations of
human beings in which newcomers to the scene are initiated into the world they
inhabit’. The liberal political philosopher Hannah Arendt said education
provides an opportunity for society both to preserve and to renew its
intellectual inheritance through an intergenerational conversation.
One of the
principal tasks of education is to teach children about the world as it is and
how it became that way. Although society is continually changing, education
needs to acquaint young people with the legacy of the past. The term ‘learning
from the past’ is often said sneeringly - yet it is impossible for people to
engage with the future if they do not draw on the insights and knowledge from
centuries of human experience. Individuals gain an understanding of themselves
through becoming familiar with the unfolding of the human world.
In essence, the
main mission of education is to preserve the past so that the young have the
cultural and intellectual resources they need to deal with the challenges of
the future. This understanding of education as renewal stands
in direct contrast to the current trend for elevating change and
unpredictability in the currcilum. Too often in modern Anglo-American
societies, curriculum-planning is about cultivating an ethos of flexibility
towards the future; of course, the capacity to adapt is a valuable asset, but
exercising this capacity requires that we have an intellectual and moral
grounding in knowledge and past gains.
The question of
what balance education should strike between the gains of the past and the changes
of the present and the future should be a constant source of debate. Today,
however, when policymakers and pedagogues tend to be so fixated on the present
that they seek to distance education from the past, it is essential to reaffirm
the importance of a traditional humanist education. The impulse to free
education from the past is driven by a view of all ideas that are not of the
moment as old-fashioned and irrelevant. Yet preserving the past through
education does not mean uncritically accepting the world as it is; it means
assuming adult responsibility for the world into which the young are
integrated. The aim should be to acquaint the young with the world as it is so
that they have the intellectual resources necessary for renewing it, for moving
the human conversation forward.
A liberal humanist
education is underpinned by a conviction that children are the rightful heirs
to the achievements and legacy of the past. It is precisely because education
gives meaning to the human experience that it needs to be valued in its own
right. One of the principal characteristics of education should be a lack of
interest in any ulterior purpose. That does not mean that it is uninterested in
developments affecting children and society; it means that it regards transmitting
the cultural and intellectual achievements of humanity to children as its
defining mission. Once society is able to uphold an education system that
values itself and the acquisition of knowledge, policymakers and the public can
start thinking about what practical steps might be required to deal with
current challenges in the classroom.
No comments:
Post a Comment