The commitment to the sanctity of the individual undergirds the institutions we inherited from the Revolution and Civil War
By Spengler
The
bicentennial of Soren Kierkegaard's birth passed on May 5 unremarked by the
political caste, although a dozen scholarly festivals quietly honored his
anniversary. That is a hallmark of our intellectual poverty. The casual reader
knows the Danish philosopher as the midnight reading of angst-ridden
undergraduates and the stuff of existential pop psychology.
That is
a sad outcome, for Kierkegaard is one of most rigorous philosophers, despite
his exhortative style. He asserted the primary of passion, not in the vulgar
sense of aroused emotions, but as the primary ontological substance from which
our world is built. In a passion-torn world, we should ignore the pop versions
and read him more closely.
If
asked, "Who is your favorite political philosopher?," as were the
Republican candidates in the 1980 presidential primary, I would have answered,
"Kierkegaard." (Actually, it's Franz Rosenzweig, but no-one has heard
of him).
Of
course, I would have lost. Passion is passé. Kierkegaard's outlook is close to
that of the radical Protestants who fought the American Revolution and the
Civil War, but at odds with the main currents of modern conservative thought,
that is, classical political rationalism and Catholic natural law theory.
Kierkegaard still has a redoubt at St Olaf's College in Minnesota, which
sponsors translations and maintains a library of scholarly materials, and a few
other Protestant institutions. But one never hears his name in a political context.
Closer
to the conservative mainstream is my friend Peter Berkowitz in his 2012
book Constitutional Conservatism: Liberty, Self-Government, and
Political Moderation. As Stanley Kurtz summarized his view at National
Review, "By moderation Berkowitz means something a bit different than the
everyday use of the word, otherwise Buckley and Reagan wouldn't qualify.
Political moderation, says Berkowitz, "doesn't mean selling out causes or
making a principle of pragmatism." A true understanding of moderation can
even dictate strong stances and bold opposition to popular movements. Real
political moderation, Berkowitz explains, means balancing worthy yet competing
principles and putting them effectively into practice." As a matter of
practice, Berkowitz "calls on conservatives to make a peace of sorts with
both the sexual revolution and the fundamentals of the New Deal welfare state,
without, on the other hand, surrendering either their fundamental principles or
their core battles."
There is much wisdom in Berkowitz's view. Still,
I disagree with him on two grounds.
First:
Whether we think it expedient or not, there is ultimately no compromise with
the so-called sexual revolution, because it eventually will kill us: if we fail
to subordinate sexual passion to family life, we will join the demographic
death-spiral that likely will reduce Europe's population by nearly half, from
today's 767 million to just 395 million at the end of this century, with nearly
half of the survivors over the age of 60. There is no risk in not putting up a
fight. I elaborated this argument in my 2011 book How Civilizations Die and
in reviews of recent books by the Catholic writers Mary Eberstadt and Robert P George.
Second:
Acts of passion won us the right to be moderate, temperate compromising in the
first place. America's founders pledged their lives, fortunes and sacred honor
to the revolutionary cause at a moment when they enjoyed more freedom as
Englishmen than the citizens of any other country in the world, and when
taxation without representation did not prevent them from living in peace and
relative prosperity. Never before or again in modern history did men of
property and station make such a reckless gamble. In fact, most of the signers
of the Declaration of Independence were impoverished by the war, and many would
have hanged if the American cause had failed. This supremely immoderate act was
motivated by a passion for liberty, mostly with a religious foundation.
America
was founded by Puritans fleeing Europe's collective suicide in the Thirty Years
War, and it became a magnet for German as well as English Protestant radicals
who had no stake in the European system that emerged from it. They had lived
through the catastrophic failures of European society and were ready to take
great risks to create something better.
All the
more so was the Civil War an act of passion. 750,000 Americans died, including
465,000 Union soldiers. The Southern secession threatened the freedom of
northerners not at all, and impinged only marginally on their prosperity, yet
they died in now-incomprehensible numbers to free slaves. They marched to Julia
Ward Howe's gloss on Isaiah 63, with its apocalyptic image of a God in
bloodstained garments trampling the nations in a wine vat. Lincoln evoked the
biblical God of Justice in his Second Inaugural commitment to pursue victory no
matter what the cost.
Even if
every drop of blood drawn by the lash had to be repaid by one drawn by the
sword, the judgments of the Almighty were true and righteous altogether,
Lincoln said. More immoderate words than the never were uttered by an American
leader. Lincoln didn't expect people to like them, as he wrote to Thurlow Weed:
"Men are not flattered by being shown that there is a difference of
purpose between the Almighty and them. To deny it, though, in this case would
be to deny that there is a God governing the world." Modern conservatives
often cite Edmund Burke's defense of English moderation against the destructive
passions of revolutionary France. That is well and good, but Burke was a
bystander to our great events. Burke supported the American Revolution, but
from a comfortable seat in the English parliament, not from a hut at Valley
Forge.
These
are historical observations, to be sure, and one can only object that if
Alexander had listened to Aristotle, or George III had listened to Edmund
Burke, or Jefferson Davis had listened to Lincoln, these terrible things need
not have taken place. All the more so should we preach moderation, one might
argue on the strength of the historical record, to avert repetitions of
impassioned disaster. The German refugee scholar Leo Strauss, an inspiration to
many secular conservatives, saw in classical moderation an antidote to the
destruction passions unleashed by Nazism.
All the
history lessons in the world will not persuade the passionately moderate.
Because we cannot re-run the tapes of the events, arguments from history never
can be definitive.
That is
why philosophy is indispensable as a guide to understanding history, and why
Kierkegaard is an important of political philosopher. Consider his approach to
the paradox of Socrates, in contrast to Leo Strauss' "esoteric"
reading. We have three quite different portraits of the philosopher. In
addition to Plato's sage, there is the comic playwright Aristophanes'
derogatory depiction of an impudent meddler, as well as the soldier Xenophon's
picture of Socrates as an avuncular character who dispenses advice on
commonplace matters, something like an Athenian Mark Twain.
Kierkegaard
and Strauss both tried to derive the real Socrates from these conflicting
accounts, but in radically different ways. Strauss argued that Socrates taught
a public version for the unwashed masses and an esoteric version to be
understood by true philosophers who can read between the lines. Plato's recommendations
in The Republic to hold wives in common, for example, should
be understood as a reduction to absurdity, according to Strauss. Subsequent
academic criticism has not been kind to Strauss' esotericism (see, for example,
Moshe Halbertal's 2007 book Concealment and Revelation). The
trouble with the esoteric argument is that it gives the analyst unlimited
license to project his own views onto the hapless subject of investigation.
Kierkegaard
in his doctoral dissertation on irony proposes a startling solution: all three
portraits of Socrates are true. He was the meddler who roused Athenian youth
against their elders, and the avuncular interlocutor of practical men, and the
investigator of Parmenides' theory of being. Kierkegaard asks, "But what was
Socrates actually like? ... The answer is: Socrates' existence is irony ...
Along with Xenophon, one can certainly assume that Socrates was fond of walking
around and talking with all sorts of people because every external thing or
event is an occasion for the ever quick-witted ironist; along with Plato, one
can certainly let Socrates touch on the idea."
The
actual Socrates lived and argued in an Athens already ruined by 27 years of war
with Sparta, its empire shattered, its allies dispersed, its culture demoralized.
Socrates,
according to Kierkegaard, was an ironist rather than a prophet: he looked
backward to criticize past failures, but could not look forward to propose a
remedy to these failures, for remedy there was none. The Athens of Socrates'
generation already was doomed. The greatest mind of the subsequent generation,
namely Aristotle, could do nothing better than tutor Alexander the Great, the
butcher of the Greek city-states and the gravedigger of their culture.
The
weakness in classical political rationalism, in Kierkegaard's view, is simply
this: the classical rationalists were the hapless losers of the great political
and intellectual battles of the turn of the 5th century BCE, a momentary
efflorescence of intellectual criticism that came too late to count. That may
explain why Socrates chose to drink poison rather than abandon his homeland.
Kierkegaard's
portrait of Socrates the ironist offers a corrective to the usual way Plato's
hero is presented, as a source of eternal verities. As a philosopher, though,
Kierkegaard accomplished something far more important. I recommend Michael
Wyschogrod's Kierkegaard and Heidegger: the Ontology of Being,
available in electronic edition through Questia.com. Prof Wyschogrod is celebrated for his
religious writings - Rabbi Lord Jonathan Sacks told me once that his work is
the closest thing that Jews have to a systematic theology - but Wyschogrod
still considers his 1954 volume on Kierkegaard and Heidegger his most important
book. It is not really possible provide an adequate summary of his view in a
short essay. To attempt violates the spirit of philosophy, which demands that
the learner live through the problems from the beginning. In the hope of
stirring interest in Wyschogrod's superb book, though, I will do my best.
From
the Greeks we inherit two conundrums which tormented philosophers for the next
millennium and a half. Both involve the concept of Being, the most elusive
notion in abstract thought. It is something that all of creation must possess,
but seems impossible to define.
A
generation prior to Socrates, Parmenides taught that all things partake of
Being, concluding that there could only be one Big Thing. Multiplicity and
diversity were mere illusions. To say that A has a form of Being distinct from
B is the same as to say that A partakes of Non-Being with respect to B. But
Non-Being is something that we can neither utter nor envision, Parmenides taught:
the moment we attempt to think about Non-Being, we are thinking about something,
and every something partakes of Being. Without Non-Being we cannot distinguish
A from B, and thus Parmenides claims that there cannot be many things, but only
one thing. The classic exposition of this problem is Plato's dialogue
"Parmenides," recounting a conversation between the young Socrates
and the older philosopher. I have never been sure whether to read this as a
treatise in ontology or an Athenian precursor to Abbott and Costello's
"Who's on First?" routine. Both ways of reading the dialogue probably
are right. Modern logical philosophers, to be sure, dismiss Parmenides'
argument as word-play, but that is too glib.
The
second paradox involves the analysis of Being. As St Thomas Aquinas taught,
there are two components to Being. The first is the essence of a thing, namely
what it is (a fish or a bird, for example); the second is whether the thing
exists at all. Everything must have an essence, or the qualities that make it a
recognizable object. But not all essences exist, for example, Every Flavored
Beans or Floo Powder. We can define magical things with great precision, but
that doesn't bring them any closer to existence.
That is
why Aquinas asserted that existence precedes essence. That was also the meaning
of "existentialism," long before Sartre degraded the idea into the
bland assertion that we can define our essence to be whatever we want it to be.
More paradox lurks in the tall grass, though. Just what is existence? Once we
attempt to define "existence," we enquiring about the essence of
existence, and down we go into the rabbit hole once again. That is why modern
logicians dismiss the whole business as a word game.
But we
cannot walk away from the issue of Being. As Kierkegaard explained, what we
cannot evade is the problem of our Being. We should consider our condition as
mortal humans who are caught between mortal existence and eternity. We live in
irresoluble, sometimes unbearable tension between the pull of the temporal and
the eternal. We can shut mortality out of mind, to be sure, but the specter of
eternity will creep up on us one way or another. How we stand with respect to
eternity ultimately defines our Being. This is not an intellectual exercise (our
intellect can spit out any number of possibilities), but an impassioned stance.
Because our life is circumscribed by mortality, and our Being is an
irresolvable tension between eternity and mortality, it is our passion that
defines us - for better or worse.
What
Kierkegaard teaches us is that we cannot deny passion. This can take the form
of an impassioned move towards the Eternal, or a perverse turn towards tribal
fanaticism. Stripped of its religious content, Kierkegaard's existentialism
terminates with Martin Heidegger or Jean-Paul Sartre, who leave angst-ridden
humanity to invent its own identity. Heidegger defended Nazism as the authentic
expression of German identity in his time. He "solved" the problem of
Non-Being by equating it with boredom, perversion and destruction, an idea he
cribbed from Goethe's Mephistopheles (who in turn cribbed it from
Ecclesiastes). Sartre opened a Pandora's Box of self-invention that inspired
the cultural meltdown of the 1960s. It is easy to see why reasonable people would
prefer supposed eternal verities of the Greeks to Kierkegaard's powder-keg of
passion.
The
trouble is that the Greeks, like today's Europeans, died out for lack of
interest in their own lives. The Europeans for the most part are phlegmatic,
rational, dispassionate and moderate, immune to the blandishments of the
tribalism that landed them into two world wars during the past century, and
estranged from the religion of their forbears. The Europeans, one might say,
are Stoics, adherents of the philosophy that prevailed in the Hellenic world
during the three centuries following the Alexandrine conquest. And like the
Greeks, they are dying out from their own infertility. By the time the Romans
came along, the Greeks couldn't field a dozen regiments of phalanx-men.
Kierkegaard
helps us to understand the passions of our opponents when they descend into
despair and nihilism. More importantly: He reminds us that that an impassioned
commitment to the sanctity of the individual undergirds the institutions we
inherited from the Revolution and Civil War.
We must
renew this commitment or lose them.
No comments:
Post a Comment