P2P is not flawed
because it's hard to implement; it's hard to implement because it's a paragon
of moral illogic
by Rajan Menon
It is now a commonplace belief that a worldwide
diffusion of human rights norms occurred following the Cold War, creating a
consensus favoring humanitarian intervention. The cachet acquired by
the “Responsibility to Protect” (R2P) is proffered as proof of this
proposition.
This is wishful thinking. Armed
humanitarian interventions since the aftermath of the Cold War have been
selective, poorly executed, strategically naive, morally incoherent and even
dangerous. Far from reflecting, let alone having contributed to, a global
consensus, they have been divisive. This is so not because the world has just
done it wrong at this early stage of R2P awareness; it is so because of flaws
in the concept itself.
The widespread support for R2P
as evidenced in official speeches and government and UN documents is profoundly
misleading. R2P cannot withstand tough tests that could theoretically transform
it into a template for future action. The reason is that when wars in support
of (supposedly) transcendent ideals entail significant costs and risks, the
major democratic powers—above all the United States—whose involvement is
essential will pull back, not least because their citizens are far less
enamored of such odysseys than are the high priests of humanitarian intervention.
The latter see altruistic sacrifice undertaken by states in the name of their
societies on behalf of others who are not their own citizens as moral, but they
are dismissive of the notion that protecting and pursuing sovereign
self-interest can ever be virtuous or moral as well. The assumption that
disinterestedness is what qualifies action as moral is a form of ethical
illiteracy. R2P is fundamentally flawed not because it can’t be implemented; it
can’t be implemented because it is fundamentally flawed.
By the latter half of the
1990s, an impassioned debate arose on how the world could best respond to mass
atrocities resulting from governments’ cruelties or incapacities. By then,
several bloody post-Cold War conflagrations had occurred, and the response was,
insofar as proponents of humanitarian intervention were concerned, dismaying.
NATO’s three-week bombardment of Bosnian Serb redoubts brought Slobodan
Milosevic to the bargaining table, enabling the 1995 Dayton Accords to freeze
Bosnia’s civil war. But what emerged was a post-conflict polity that granted
the Serbs much of their territorial gains and consisted of separate ethnic
enclaves. Moreover, it took three years of ethnic cleansing, mass rape,
concentration camps and the shelling of towns to get to Dayton. Bosnian Serb
troops exposed the fecklessness of NATO and the United Nations as they
assaulted or captured the “safe areas” that the unfortunately named UN
Protection Force (UNPROFOR) had vowed to defend. Some 100,000 people were
slaughtered in Bosnia. Prognostications of a burgeoning planetary concord on
human rights sounded surreal, not least because the Bosnian war followed an
even bigger disaster in Rwanda.
In 1994, Hutu nationalists,
many massed in marauding, machete-wielding gangs called the Interahamwe,
butchered some 800,000 people, the overwhelming majority ethnic Tutsi. Though
the killers would likely have scattered at the sight of a robust military force
sent from without, the cavalry never came, the supposed post-Cold War salience
of universal human rights notwithstanding.1 Indeed, once Belgium summoned
home its soldiers serving in the UN peacekeeping contingent (UNAMIR) after ten
were killed, other countries did the same. Belgium’s government fretted that it
would be shamed were others to fill the void. It needn’t have worried: No state
stepped forward, and the Clinton Administration, memories of “Blackhawk Down”
Mogadishu still fresh, opposed UNAMIR’s expansion even though it contained no
American soldiers. Thus a minimal force of 2,500 in August 1993 fell to a
paltry 250 in April 1994. The genocide was followed by claims that nothing
could have been done, despite scant evidence that any effort was made to
explore doing what was later blithely declared undoable.
These outcomes would not
surprise anyone who understands that states seldom take military action in
support of abstract principles except when important interests are also at
issue, the risks small, and the cost tolerable. These were scarcely the first
times governments stood by despite incontrovertible evidence of ongoing mass
murder: Consider the Holocaust or the Armenian genocide. States have even
condemned interventions, diplomatic or military, that stopped massacres:
Witness the American and Chinese opposition to the Indian army’s march into
East Pakistan in 1971 and to Vietnam’s 1978 invasion of Cambodia, which toppled
the Khmer Rouge. Strategic calculations, as usual, trumped human rights, even,
in the latter episode, during the bleeding-heart presidency of Jimmy Carter.
The Carter Administration, with Chinese support, persisted in its macabre
policy by enabling the continued occupation by Pol Pot’s “Democratic Kampuchea”
of Cambodia’s General Assembly seat. The Administration of Ronald Reagan,
Carter’s successor, opposed investigations into the Khmer Rouge’s crimes, while
the Ford Administration favored the movement’s inclusion in any Cambodian
political settlement.
Given this background, NATO’s
belated intervention in the Bosnian war galvanized believers in humanitarian
intervention. It seemed to vindicate their conviction that, pace realism,
states are moved by altruism and ideals as well as by interests. The Bosnian
intervention then shaped American conduct in the Kosovo conflict. By 1997, Serb
forces were battling the Kosovo Liberation Army (KLA), which, thanks in part to
NATO’s intervention in Bosnia, had sidelined Ibrahim Rugova, the proponent of
non-violent resistance. The KLA saw armed resistance with a twist as the path
to Kosovo’s independence. The twist was this: KLA operations, which were not
limited to military targets, aimed to provoke the Serbs to excess, the better
to induce external humanitarian intervention. The calculation proved sound. In
1999, NATO airstrikes forced Serbia’s capitulation, paving the way for Kosovo
to become a protectorate of the United Nations and European Union and,
eventually in 2008, independent.
The Kosovo war, though lauded
by humanitarian interventionists, was not without its problems. Realizing that
Russia and China would veto Security Council resolutions favoring intervention,
NATO acted independently, eliciting accusations that the campaign was illegal
and might set a precedent for unilateral interventions and end-runs around the
UN. Was the world’s most powerful alliance, led by the world’s most powerful
state, now in the business of hijacking human rights to justify wars of
self-interest? Supporters of the Kosovo war answered that the UN should not be
the sole or necessarily the essential forum for authorizing action against mass
killings because that would allow a single permanent member of the Security
Council to block a humanitarian intervention. They also parsed the difference
between legality and legitimacy, pushing for a new trend in customary law that
would eventually align statutory international law with current, presumably
more advanced, conceptions of international morality.
This was the context in which
then-UN Secretary General Kofi Annan called for an alternative between inaction
(Rwanda) and freelancing outside UN auspices (Kosovo). The Canadian government responded
by sponsoring the International Commission on Intervention and State
Sovereignty (ICISS), a group of global notables convened under the chairmanship
of the former Australian Foreign Minister Gareth Evans and the veteran Algerian
diplomat Mohammed Sahnoun. The Commission’s 2001 report produced the elaborate
doctrine known as “The Responsibility to Protect”, which has since sired a
cottage industry of conferences, books and articles, research centers and much
controversy besides.
R2P won wide acceptance in a
short time, showing once again how good intentions can trump realistic concerns
related to outcomes. R2P was endorsed in the General Assembly’s “Outcome
Document” adopted at the UN’s sixtieth anniversary in 2005 (the “World Summit”)
and reaffirmed by the Assembly in 2009. Eleven Security Council resolutions
have since invoked it in such places as Darfur, Southern Sudan, the Ivory
Coast, Liberia, Libya, Syria and Mali. And R2P supporters from the start
portrayed NATO’s 2011 UN-sanctioned war in Libya as an exemplary instance of
its application, providing yet another example of feel-good intentions
outweighing consideration of consequences to be suffered by others.
R2P attempts to reconcile the
perspectives of two different constituencies. The first comprises states and
organizations that aver that human beings have certain inalienable rights,
above all not to be killed or harmed without just cause, and that the
“international community” has an obligation to protect them when these rights
are violated. The second consists of states that see sovereignty as fundamental
both to international law and to international order. They fear that norms and
formulas that facilitate armed intervention within countries will only produce
more war and instability.
R2P’s originators anticipated
that any prescription perceived as proposing lax criteria for the use of force
would be dead on arrival, so the ICISS report and follow-on publications of its
ilk have bowed before the shrine of sovereignty. They affirm that the
obligation to protect people rests in the first instance with the governments
that have jurisdiction over them, but they add that when a state cannot or will
not protect human rights, the responsibility shifts to the international community,
which means, ideally, the UN girded with Security Council authorization, or in
a pinch regional organizations if they promise subsequently to seek UNSCR
approval. R2P proponents take pains to explain that the concept is not a
pretext for military intervention. Force, Gareth Evans tirelessly reiterates,
should be used only during human rights emergencies and only following the
failure of diplomacy, mediation, naming and shaming, and sanctions. Even then,
he stresses, feasibility, risks, proportionality and the prospects for success
must be weighed. (There is more than a dollop of just war theory in R2P;
Augustine and Aquinas would be proud.) R2P’s expositors also recommend various
preventive measures: early-warning mechanisms, pre-crisis mediation, peacekeeping,
economic assistance and post-conflict reconstruction.2
Yet the reassurances that force
would be a rare, last-ditch response have not placated critics, for several
reasons. R2P’s pre-intervention prescriptions merely repeat existing remedies
and add nothing to diplomacy’s toolkit. What’s new is the casuistry of
reframing and diminishing sovereignty in order to legitimize altruistic armed
intervention in defense of the abstract rights that most political communities
agree upon in theory. Given R2P’s emphasis on feasibility and the chances for
success, weak states are its most likely proving grounds; powerful ones need
not fear, no matter the magnitude of their misdeeds. Because idealism and power
are inextricably intertwined, with the latter frequently corrupting the former,
R2P provides powerful states one script for playing the Good Samaritan when
intervention promotes their interests, and another for eschewing or opposing
aid when it doesn’t.
R2P’s defenders see this
indictment as reflecting hyperbole or misunderstanding, or as the artifice of
dictators who declaim about sovereignty and legality but in truth seek to avoid
accountability. Yes, dictators have every reason to avoid accountability, but
it doesn’t really matter which side is right. What matters is that in a world
of diverse polities and cultures, such objections and anxieties have sufficient
appeal to prevent the doctrine from acquiring the universal pragmatic
applicability its supporters seek. Many states have signed on to R2P, but it does
not follow that they will stand behind its sovereignty-eroding features when it
is proposed as a plan for military action.
R2P is an epiphenomenon in that
it reflects a larger challenge to Westphalian/Weberian conceptions of
sovereignty by liberal internationalists who want to tie state sovereignty to
legitimacy, which in turn is made dependent on how governments treat their citizens.
Sovereignty in this view is a means to defend people and to improve their
lives, not a license for leaders to do what they wish for reasons of state.
This perspective now permeates the discourse of international lawyers,
philosophers, political scientists, ethicists, activists and journalists who
believe that liberal democratic norms are benignly rearranging the relationship
between the state and the citizen, constraining the former and empowering the
latter.
This worldview emanates from a
distinctive variant of liberalism that the Norwegian political scientist George
Sørensen calls the “liberalism of imposition” (as opposed to “the liberalism of
restraint”).3 Its adherents reject the realist account of world politics,
seeing it as—among other things—statist, preoccupied with competition and
conflict, dismissive of the multiple manifestations of international
cooperation, and uncommitted to human rights and justice because of its
singular focus on state security interests.4 Revolutionary liberals, as I
call them, are by contrast in the business of studying and fostering
cooperation—among states, with international organizations and non-governmental
entities playing a central role. Part of their agenda of collective action for
the common good involves advancing human rights and justice. This can be done
in many ways; humanitarian intervention is just one of them. Revolutionary
liberals see the United States as having a special, even unique, role in
enabling this and other forms of collective action because of the values
America embodies and the still unrivalled power it wields.
Unsurprisingly, revolutionary
liberals and neoconservatives have often been of like mind on humanitarian
intervention, nation-building and democracy promotion. Both are historicist,
even teleological, in temperament. Both share a near-providential notion of
America’s mission. Both are drawn to schemes of social engineering: the
redesigning of other countries and even the international order itself. In
short, they have more in common than they care to admit with the millenarian
and utopian ideologies (radical Islamism, Marxism and fascism) that they abhor
as illiberal. Prominent personalities from both camps demanded intervention in
Libya (and many also supported the Iraq War), applauded when it occurred, and
have criticized the Obama Administration for not arming the anti-Assad
insurgents in Syria and for its unwillingness to contemplate even bolder moves.5
However adept it is at
generating applause lines from the good-heartedly unreflective, revolutionary
liberalism’s paradigm is problematic in several respects. Take the idea that
the Soviet Union’s collapse, democracy’s growing appeal and globalization’s
myriad effects have together yielded benign new norms with a universal ambit.
This claim amounts to a solipsism. It also assumes that the connectivity
created by the worldwide flows of commerce and information will eventually
enable a global convergence in normative values. This is wrongheaded, and one
need not have read Johann Gottfried Herder or Isaiah Berlin to see why. China,
Brazil, India, Indonesia, South Africa and Russia—to name but a few major
countries—are all enmeshed in myriad international transactions, but they
reject the proposition that sovereignty ought to be redefined so that states
become legitimate targets of military intervention (or even other forms of
coercion) when they contravene what certain states have certified, for
themselves at least, as transcendent norms.
As a case in point, Brazil’s
2011 proposal for “the responsibility while protecting” does not, as some
believe, seek simply to limit the damage done to noncombatants during armed
interventions. Its more important goals, in the wake of the Libya war, are to
better control missions authorized for protecting civilians so that they do not
evolve into ones of regime change, and to restrict further the conditions under
which force can be used. Likewise, the decisions of India and Brazil to support
a General Assembly resolution condemning Bashar al-Assad’s government should
not obscure their reservations about R2P.
States have long favored the
principle of human rights, so long as it is restricted to words and documents.
It is also true that the idea that sovereignty involves duties as well as
rights has gained wide support, and not just in the West. But when it comes to
common criteria for permitting military action to save lives, the consensus
invariably breaks down on both theoretical and practical grounds. Brazil and India
abstained in the Security Council on the no-fly zone resolution aimed at Libya
(as did Germany). That decision reflected a wider suspicion that humanitarian
intervention, no matter its paeans to justice, will be applied inconsistently,
and inevitably by the strong against the weak. This underscores the ultimate
problem facing humanitarian intervention. Countries differ on too many
dimensions (power and wealth, historical experience, culture and religion,
political ideology and national identity) and are too numerous to allow a
common standard for authorizing military coercion in support of human rights.
As was apparent in the General Assembly debates on R2P at the “World Summit”,
what is agreed upon will be general, qualified, non-binding and susceptible to
self-interested interpretation. That is because many weaker states cannot get
good answers as to who exactly gets to decide whether and when a state has
failed to meet its responsibilities, and how the decision would be taken. What
would prevent the definition of “responsibility” from expanding and eroding
sovereignty? How would people in “rescued” countries hold accountable a UN
that, via R2P, acquires power over their lives? There simply are no good
answers to these questions, and there cannot be.
As a consequence of these
concerns, the “World Summit” Outcome Document put R2P in a tighter harness. The
Security Council’s sign-off was made a prerequisite for its implementation. The
international community was required only to “encourage and advise” states to
discharge their responsibility to protect. There was no explicit reference to
enforcement by military means. Many R2P proponents were disappointed by this
lowest-common-denominator declaration, but diluted formulations were the only
ones Russia, China and varoius other countries were prepared to accept. Adding
in the requirement for UNSCR approval means that their vetoes can prevent
R2P-backed campaigns against friendly states and, more important, take the
North Caucasus, Tibet and Xinjiang off the R2P map altogether. The same goes
for sensitive zones in India, Brazil, Thailand, Burma, Nigeria, Indonesia and a
dozen other states. So much for the displacement of realpolitik by
increasingly influential, universal human rights norms.
The world has not obliged
revolutionary liberals. Raison d’état is resilient: Practical
interests shape what states do, not abstract ideals. The United States and its
democratic allies are not exceptions to this rule. When it comes to R2P, they,
just as China and Russia have, will block punitive measures against friendly
governments. Imagine that the so-called Arab Spring makes a delayed appearance
in Saudi Arabia. Would the Saudis ever face a Security Council resolution with
“R2P” in it? Would the United States, Britain or France back an R2P resolution
occasioned by Israel’s use of force in the West Bank or Gaza? No and no.
Those who doubt this might
ponder recent events in Bahrain, where a Sunni-run state lords over its Shi‘a
majority. The Obama Administration deemed Qaddafi’s violence against the Libyan
opposition R2P-worthy but has been unmoved by the Bahraini regime’s repression
of unarmed protestors. Nor is Washington’s stance likely to change so long as
the U.S. Fifth Fleet is headquartered in Bahrain. Saudi Arabia played a
decisive role in mobilizing Arab support for UNSCR 1973, which authorized the
intervention against Qaddafi; but it sent troops into Bahrain to crush the
Shi‘a rebellion three days before NATO’s intervention in Libya. Qatar, too,
mustered Arab League support for the move against Qaddafi and provided combat
aircraft to supplement NATO’s Libya intervention, but its troops joined the
Saudi gendarmes’ march into Manama. What mattered for the Gulf monarchies was
preventing the rise of a Shi‘a-dominated state in Bahrain aligned with Iran.
Self-determination and liberty could wait—indefinitely. Egyptian security
forces killed 840 unarmed civilians and injured some 6,000 during the uprising
against Mubarak; no major government invoked R2P. Had Mubarak survived and
unleashed his army in full, would he have shared Qaddafi’s R2P-tinged fate? Not
likely. Strong horses don’t attract R2P attention; only weak or vulnerable ones
do.
Powerful democracies have long
been willing to countenance the killing and expulsions of people and to arm
governments that commit such acts. Consider some examples. Turkey’s war against
the PKK has killed thousands of civilians since 1984 and displaced another
386,000. In 1988–89, Saddam Hussein gassed and deported thousands of Kurds,
killing as many as 100,000 of them, and systematically razed their towns and
villages. But Washington turned a blind eye because the Iraqi dictator was then
providing a useful service by fighting Khomeini’s Iran.
Consider, too, that between
Indonesia’s annexation of East Timor in 1975 and the 1999 UN-sanctioned,
Australian-led intervention, 18,600 East Timorese civilians were killed, and
another 102,800 died from war-related hunger and disease, with the vast
majority of the fatalities occurring before 1999. Australia was rightly
complimented for leading the multilateral force that helped bring stability,
and eventually independence, to East Timor. But the Australian government, its
own documents have since revealed, knew that Indonesia was preparing to conquer
East Timor in 1975, may have provided tacit approval, and certainly was willing
to arm Suharto’s government in the years preceding the annexation. Not
only was Australia the only major Western democracy to officially recognize the
annexation; Gareth Evans, then its Foreign Minister, signed a deal in 1989 with
his Indonesian counterpart, Ali Alatas, giving Australian energy companies
access to the seabed off East Timor. As for the United States, it armed the
Indonesian army for years, even though between 500,000 and one million people
perished following the 1965 coup that brought Suharto to power. It is now clear
that Indonesia’s conquest of East Timor occurred with the Ford Administration’s
foreknowledge—and acquiescence. American arms sales to Indonesia rose
substantially after its occupation of East Timor. Britain’s dealings with
Suharto followed a similar pattern.
The point here is not to
condemn particular states for their selective moral outrages or for putting
interests before ethics. This is what states of all stripes tend to do. It’s
not that they never act in defense of principles or altruistically; it’s that
they don’t do so when important interests point another way, or when the costs
and hazards of defending them are deemed prohibitive. R2P boosters and
revolutionary liberals will reply that the inability to defend basic values
everywhere does not mean they can’t be defended when possible. Examples of
supposedly successful action (Bosnia, Kosovo, East Timor and Libya) are trotted
out, perhaps supplemented by Emerson’s quip about consistency’s allure for
“little minds.” But given the realities of power, what this riposte concedes is
that if a weak and ally-bereft state kills its citizens, it risks falling into
the R2P file and facing armed intervention. If not, then not—which brings us to
the problem of moral hazard inherent in R2P.
The prospect of an external
humanitarian intervention, as noted earlier, led the KLA to adopt tactics that
bordered on terrorism, and Serbia in turn to adopt tactics that resembled
migratory genocide. In Libya, once the UN-sanctioned machinery of intervention
began to move, anti-Qaddafi insurgents had no reason to compromise and Qaddafi
had no motivation to hold back. R2P presents a theoretical continuum of
measures with armed intervention at one end, but engaged antagonists know that
the various intermediate steps can easily and rapidly be skipped, the continuum
collapsed, and the concept applied expansively. That encourages opposition
forces to magnify violence to attract and suborn outside help, and it
encourages embattled regimes to accelerate efforts at repression before
external intervention can be agreed upon and implemented. In short, the
prospect of R2P interventions can easily make bad situations worse.
Consider Syria in this light.
The Assad government has certainly slaughtered enough of its own citizens to
attract R2P attention. But no major power has proposed armed intervention or
even arming the insurgents in a dramatic or open way. Why? Because, unlike
Qaddafi, Assad has the equipment to make the establishment of a no-fly zone,
let alone use of ground troops, a very hazardous venture. Syria also has
reliable supporters and arms suppliers in Russia and Iran, and Beijing has
joined Moscow in scuttling successive Security Council resolutions aimed at the
Assad regime. Russia and China had not forgotten that in Libya what began as an
R2P intervention to protect civilians turned quickly into one aimed at regime
change. It’s impossible to prove, being a counterfactual, but had an R2P
intervention in Syria ever seemed possible to the combatants, it might well
have made the carnage worse by quickening the tempo of killing.
In states’ calculations about
intervention it is not the magnitude of the atrocities that matters. Four other
considerations count for more. The first is the likely ease of the operation,
itself a function of the perpetrator’s power. Seen thus, using force against,
say, China or Russia becomes unimaginable even if they were to massacre many
thousands of civilians, as Russia did in Chechnya in the 1990s. The second is
whether powerful countries’ important interests are at issue. In Rwanda, they
were not. A third is whether the offender has allies willing to block UN
resolutions proposing intervention, or to dilute those calling for sanctions or
peacekeeping forces. Thanks to backing from China and Russia, the Sudanese
government could cynically shape the size, composition and mandate of the
Darfur peacekeeping force. Fourth, would-be interveners will desist when a
conflict’s complexity and scale of violence produce a sense of futility or fears
of being sucked into a swamp. A case in point is the Congo. Since 1994, between
one million and 5.4 million people (a debate rages on the precise figure) have
perished there from the direct or indirect effects of war, making the loss of
life in Libya, and even Syria, pale in comparison. The UN’s peacekeeping
efforts have had the effect of a gnat biting an elephant, and indeed have in
instances made matters worse.
Those who start wars are often
confident that they know how they will end. They are just as often proved
wrong. Idealistic humanitarian interveners, a sub-species of such hubristic
planners, congratulate themselves on their high-mindedness, which leads most of
them to assume that if no self-interested motives attach to their intentions,
then no self-interested consequences can emerge from them. Of course this is
absurd.
One result of NATO’s (eventual)
decision to strike Bosnian Serb forces in 1995, very popular among the
soon-to-be-hatched R2P brood, was to alter the political balance within the Kosovar
Albanian opposition. The Dayton deal skirted Kosovo, confirming most Kosovars’
belief that the world couldn’t care less about their plight. The new context
helped the KLA but, as already noted, shaped the ferocity of its tactics. In
response, Serb forces mounted a major counterinsurgency campaign. Indeed, the
multiplication of Western calls to “do something” had the perverse effect of
inducing Slobodan Milosevic to ramp up the killings and expulsions. Once NATO
started bombing, Milosevic moved even faster and more ruthlessly to quash the
KLA, but NATO still limited itself to airpower and restricted pilots to safe
altitudes. The result? In less than three months after NATO began bombing,
Serbian troops killed some 10,000 people in Kosovo and drove another 1.4
million from their homes. The shallowness of the alliance’s commitment to
humanitarian principles was revealed when it chose to conduct a campaign that
would produce minimal, ideally zero, casualties for its own soldiers, no matter
the horrendous consequences for the people it had intervened to protect.
NATO’s defenders say that it
did not do the killing and expelling, that Milosevic was responsible and that
he would have done what he did anyway. Yes, the Serbian leadership
unquestionably bears responsibility; yes, atrocities occurred before NATO
acted; but there can be no doubt that the scale and duration of Serbian
atrocities owed much to NATO’s intervention. The self-exculpatory claim that
what happened would have happened is unpersuasive.
It is also worth noting in
passing what the Kosovar victory enabled—a set of concerns almost universally
ignored in Western accounts of the war. NATO defended the intervention as a
response to killings and ethnic cleansing, but after the war Albanians killed many
Serb civilians and forced thousands of Serbs and Roma from their homes even as
NATO troops (organized as KFOR) were moving in to secure Kosovo. The KLA
maintained detention centers in Albania where several hundreds of Serbs and
other minorities, plus Albanians suspected of complicity with the Serb
authorities, were held. Some were tortured, others killed—in some cases after
their organs were removed for sale by Albanian criminal networks.6 High-ranking
KLA officials participated in some of these activities. Before the war, in
those parts of Kosovo not controlled by Serb forces, criminal clans, again
involving KLA leaders, seized industries, natural resources and property,
foreshadowing the massive corruption and criminality that mark Kosovo today.
None of this ever excited much passion in Brussels or Washington; nor were
European governments welcoming toward refugees fleeing Kosovo. Their focus was
on Serb atrocities. The KLA, which had gained in stature partly because the
United States and Europe embraced it as a war partner and as the legitimate
representative of Kosovar resistance, got a pass. In humanitarian
intervention’s Manichean world of artificial passion plays, there are no shades
of gray. Unintended consequences are either ignored or blamed on others.
Libya is the most recent
instance of unintended consequences flowing from R2P adventures. The post-bellum account
of Libya by R2P enthusiasts obscures some unpleasant facts about the gap
between ideals and interests. While no sane person mourns the end of Qaddafi’s
vicious regime, the portrayal of his ouster as a victory for human rights gives
off more than a whiff of hypocrisy. European and American leaders well
understood the monstrous cruelties that marked his long rule. Yet once he
surrendered the two Libyans suspected of involvement in the Lockerbie bombing
(April 1999), abandoned his WMD programs (2003) and transmogrified from tyrant
to ally against terrorism (in British Prime Minister Tony Blair’s words), the
plot changed. Crippling sanctions on Libya were lifted in exchange for good
conduct, and the same European countries that later spearheaded the
intervention against Qaddafi were eager to receive him, to invest in Libya and
even to sell him arms worth substantial sums. (Did they imagine that the
weapons would be used for Libya’s self-defense?) Likewise, MI6 and the CIA
worked with Libyan intelligence, and Britain and the United States “rendered”
into Qaddafi’s hands members of the Libyan Armed Islamic Fighting Group. (Then
there was the embarrassing courtship of Qaddafi by the London School of
Economics; the foolish pronouncements about the progressive potential of his
regime and the reformist bent of his son, Saif al-Islam, by leading British
academics, including Anthony Giddens and David Held; and their American
counterparts’ trysts and transactions with the Jamahiriya.) This sordid past
has been forgotten, or the subject is changed, or rationalizations offered,
whenever it comes up.
At the same time, the misdeeds
of the Libyan insurgents—the bombardment of loyalist towns, the brutal slaying
of Qaddafi and his aides, the blatantly racist persecution of African
immigrants and guest workers, the execution of government troops and the
widespread revenge killings—have elicited little comment from Western leaders,
let alone condemnation. The gruesome murder of Qaddafi even occasioned a
tasteless wisecrack from Secretary of State Hillary Clinton.
The stated rationale for the
intervention was that Qaddafi, having launched a successful counteroffensive
against rebellious towns, had ordered his forces to storm Benghazi and,
presumably, murder its residents. That eastern city, Libya’s second largest,
had first raised the banner of rebellion, inspiring revolts elsewhere. Fears
mounted that a bloodbath was looming, especially after Qaddafi’s bellicose
March 17 speech directed at Benghazi. One Obama Administration official, Dennis
Ross, reportedly warned, without offering any basis for his over-the-top
calculation, that 100,000 people would be killed in Benghazi, which has a
population of one million.
Moreover, between February 18,
when the uprising began, and the March 17 no-fly zone resolution, there was
scant evidence of determined efforts to pursue the non-military steps proposed
by R2P. At an early stage in the uprising, key Western states were already
calling for Qaddafi to relinquish power. Then UN sanctions were imposed, and
the no-fly zone soon followed, clearing the way for bombings and missile
strikes and massive arms shipments to the insurgency by Qatar (joined by Kuwait
and the UAE). At no point was the campaign halted to see whether the
bombardment and missile strikes had persuaded Qaddafi to cease his attacks and
negotiate with his internal adversaries.
The Libyan campaign was another
risk-free venture, too. The world’s mightiest alliance took nine months
(March–October 2011) to defeat a besieged dictator with a rusty third-rate
military machine. An estimated 1,200–2,000 Libyans were killed prior to NATO’s
intervention; some 30,000 perished in the months following it.
Qaddafi contributed mightily to the tally, but insurgent attacks on the
regime’s strongholds and, to a much smaller extent, NATO airstrikes, also did
their part. The similarity to Kosovo in terms of the contrast between announced
goals (saving lives urgently) and results is striking. Despite the influence
revolutionary liberals attribute to human rights norms, once again the
interveners showed no inclination to take risks, even as the death toll
mounted. This attitude mirrored public opinion. Less than half of Americans
polled by Gallup supported the Libyan intervention. The numbers fell further
when they were asked about more forceful (read: dangerous) action as the
campaign dragged on. This tepidity was scarcely unique to this particular
intervention, or to Americans.
Postwar Libya is a honeycomb of
militias. Having bled and died for the revolution, they now ignore the central
government’s writ, run illicit businesses, operate protection rackets, lobby
for the return of polygamy (or just practice it anyway), murder American diplomats
and fight turf wars—all as Libyan leaders watch helplessly. Worse, the state
pays some militias to control others, thus deepening its dependence on them and
marginalizing an already feeble military and police force. But militias are not
the only problem. The historic antipathies between tribal confederations in
Tripolitania and Cyrenaica have reemerged. Radical Islamist groups have become
powerful players, particularly in Libya’s east, and intimidate and attack those
whose lifestyles, politics and religious beliefs they reject. Such is
post-Qaddafi Libya, and we have yet to mention the mayhem in Mali, which is a
direct result—via the Tuareg factor—of the Libyan war, and its potential spread
to Algeria, Niger, Burkino Faso and Mauritania.
Libya’s chaos must, of course,
be seen in perspective. The new order is young, as is the post-Qaddafi state.
Libya lacks any democratic history and was shackled by a dictatorship for
decades; its sense of statehood is also very recent, dating in earnest only
from 1951. Even in the best of all worlds, it needs time to produce a polity
that is stable, efficient and liberal. Achieving jus post bellum is
laborious, inglorious and expensive. The odds of success are long, and
outsiders engaged in the effort face numerous risks, not to mention impatient
citizens at home. Revolutionary liberals, given their faith in social
engineering, appear undaunted by any of this. Not for them are the warnings of
a Burke or an Oakeshott.
Though some advocates of
humanitarian intervention underscore the importance of jus post bellum,
their counsel hasn’t transformed policy or won public support. Once the guns
fall silent, a round of self-congratulation follows. Attention turns elsewhere.
The cameras and speechmaking move on. Postwar disappointments and outright
failures are blamed on the incompetence, corruption and culture of the locals;
never mind that the “locals” inherited a colossal mess, both because of the
consequences of the intervention and the nature of the regimes with which
intervening states sometimes did business for years. “We gave them freedom,
didn’t we? It’s not our fault if they squandered it.” That’s the stock response
when the contrast between anticipation and achievement yawns.
Another standard response is to
point to Bosnia as a success. But Bosnia’s political system illustrates the
institutionalization of ethnic cleansing. Political identity and ethnic
affiliation are inseparable, and the three main nationalities lead separate
lives. Serbs in Republika Srpska look to Serbia; Croats in the “Federation of
Bosnia and Herzegovina” to Croatia; Bosniaks look hard for any help at all,
increasingly to Turkey. This delicate construction of frozen reciprocal hatreds
has required a multi-year military deployment, first by NATO and then by the
European Union. Since Dayton, Bosnia has received more than $15 billion in
international aid, yet the unemployment rate at the end of 2012 was nearly 45
percent.
The contention that liberal
norms are reshaping received conceptions of sovereignty and creating a
consensus on humanitarian intervention amounts to the wish fathering the
thought. The reality is that what one part of the world sees as universal
concord, another sees as cover for self-interest and double standards. Armed
interventions have thus occasioned controversy, not convergence. Even those
Western governments that profess the most allegiance to humanitarian ideals
have shown themselves unwilling to pay any significant price to promote them.
Their citizens certainly do not want to foot the bills and face the dangers
involved in serving as guardians and enforcers of global justice.
The fact is that our
world is too heterogeneous to permit a consensus-based redefinition of
sovereignty or universally accepted, operationally substantive criteria for
armed intervention in response to atrocities. Selectivity and self-interest
will, perforce, reign, and that is no prolegomenon for a global agreement on
the high-voltage controversy surrounding the circumstances under which force
can legitimately override sovereignty. The search for common ground here will
be more divisive than unifying, especially when the focus moves from airy
statements to the fine print and, above all, to implementation. That is not a
bad thing, for the R2P impulse is in practice strategically obtuse, easily subverted,
prone to counterproductive outcomes, and, above all, ethically incoherent in
its foundational premises.
There is no final fix for mass
atrocities in our world, let alone one based on abstractions advanced by a
coalition of Davos poseurs and Western academics. In the end, those groups of
people vulnerable to abuse need to engage in maximum feasible self-help to
reduce their vulnerability. As for the rest of us, we can help sometimes if
we’re careful about it, and we probably should, but, said Wallace Stevens, “the
imperfect is our paradise.” So it is, and ever will be.
No comments:
Post a Comment