Some Questions with No Very Good Answers
For the ancients, man was bound
by but not wholly defined as part of nature. The studies of natural phenomena
and human affairs had to be distinct disciplines, for all of the reasons that
nature and man are distinct in kind. On this view, “political science” was a
distinct form of study from that of natural phenomena, requiring very different
assumptions and approaches. The inauguration of the modern period was marked,
among many other things, by the belief that human beings could be wholly understood
through the same methods as natural things; thus, a new “science of politics”
based upon the ideals of predictability and even control and manipulation of
human beings was seen not only as possible but greatly desirable. The modern
period also saw the reason for scientific inquiry shift from merely
understanding how nature was governed to understanding how human beings could
master it. Nature became not subject but object; and human inquiry was set not
only in service of understanding politics, but manipulating nature for
political ends.
It ought to
come as no surprise, then, that these ideas might be carried further, so that
human beings, as merely part of nature, could also be regarded as natural
objects for manipulation. Man, too, could become no longer just subject but
object. Many of the great horrors of the last century — from economic failures
of all sorts to eugenics and worse — arose from this understanding. But a new
movement today, calling itself transhumanism, carries these notions to their
logical conclusion: human beings are not only manipulable objects, but raw, manipulable material; man himself, his very form,
might be tinkered with, enhanced, and “reengineered,” like a species of crop or
livestock. What becomes of the political animal when politics seeks not to meet
his ends but to unravel them — not to serve him but to remake him?
Classical
Political Science
Science, by the dictionary’s
reckoning, has several meanings. One of those is very familiar: “the
observation, identification, description, experimental investigation, and
theoretical explanation of phenomena.” This is the kind of science we associate
with men and women in lab coats, wearing thick glasses and surrounded by test
tubes. Another definition reads that science means “knowledge, especially that gained through
experience.” This latter definition does not preclude the first, but it seems
to be more comprehensive, including experience that we might gain in settings
outside the laboratory, and settings that are less than entirely controlled. In
both these meanings — which are similar but distinct in crucial ways, as we
will see — the stress is upon knowledge.
This emphasis reflects the etymological root of our word science in the Latin word scientia and its forebear, the
Greek word episteme, both
of which mean knowledge.
The meanings of both words embrace acomprehensiveness of
human knowing: human inquiry of every kind is said to aim at scientia orepisteme. Thus, broadly speaking, for the ancients, philosophy,
theology, history — even the study of politics — were all forms of scientia.
In this
ancient, more comprehensive meaning, science
thus included not only “the investigation of natural phenomena,” but the
investigation of human phenomena. This investigation included the effort to
understand the material nature of the human body, particularly through the
science of medicine. But it also included the effort to gain knowledge of the
human condition more broadly, including an understanding of the ethical and
political dimensions that seemed essential to human life and human flourishing.
All of these, again, were considered to be a part of scientia.
Aristotle
divided this comprehensive activity of science into two parts: “theoretical”
and “practical.” The “theoretical” sciences involved the kinds of
investigations that issue in exact answers, including, among others,
mathematics and the most mathematical of the natural sciences. In contemporary
terms, the theoretical sciences would be the disciplines that design exams to
be read by Scantrons and offer courses in which students generally don’t
complain about their grades. The “practical” sciences, on the other hand,
involved a degree of inexactitude, as the subjects they study are not reducible
to predictability. Such sciences would include, broadly, the practice of
medicine, which (as the TV showHouse teaches
us weekly) can be more like detective work than like a “theoretical” science.
Above all, the practical sciences generally involve the study of human
phenomena. Humans, because of their irreducible freedom, act in ways that are
unpredictable, and thus cannot be subject to the same kind of science as we
find in the theoretical sciences.
What is
striking about this ancient understanding of science is that the theoretical sciences were so
named because they were a form of knowledge that was acquired for the sake of knowing. Theoretical
sciences involved gaining knowledge so as to understand the order and nature of
reality, without a necessary application. To be sure, there were often
applications for the theoretical sciences — for example, mathematics was used
in the design of buildings, but such forms of applied science were not to be
confused with the study of mathematics itself. At the conclusion of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle
establishes a strong contrast between the contemplative orientation of
the theoretical sciences
and the kind of knowledge gained through the practical sciences, which aim at informing human action.
This is not
to suggest, however, that the subject of theoretical sciences and the subject
of practical sciences — broadly speaking, nature on the one hand and humanity
on the other — are unrelated. For the natural order is the context in which
human activities take place: if human beings are free, they are nevertheless
constrained by the natural conditions that are the subject of the theoretical
sciences. Further, our freedom is bound by the fact that human beings possess a
nature which, by our free actions, we can distort or damage. For instance, in
matters of appetite, we can consume to excess, leading to a condition that
undermines our health. But the same is true more broadly in the moral domain:
we can act in ways that fall short or exceed right action, and thus lead to the
undermining of the human good.
To act in
accordance with our bounded freedom is to act in accordance with the virtues. It is to act in a way that
is rightly oriented toward the fulfillment of our nature, within the context of
a natural order. Virtues combine our pre-conscious dispositions and
habituations to do what is right — such as generosity, friendliness,
cleanliness, and right speech — with an intellectual ability to reason, reflect
upon, develop, and train those habituations — an ability which is itself the
virtue Aristotle callsphronesis,
or “practical wisdom.”
According to
ancient theory, the aim of the practical sciences is perhaps above all the
achievement of the virtues. The knowledge of these sciences was aimed at
informing action; in
particular, those forms of activity that hinged on our capacity to exercise
good judgment. For this reason, the practical sciences were those that aimed
not at gaining exact answers,
but at gaining sufficient understanding
of inexact conditions in areas requiring judgment or practical
wisdom. As Aristotle discloses at the outset of the Nicomachean Ethics, young people
should not engage in politics — that most architectonic of the practical
sciences — because they do not yet have an adequate fund of experience by which
to exercise good judgment. Science, in this sense, requires experience.
On the other
hand, the theoretical sciences
were not, and could not be, a source of knowledge about action. The sort of
inquiry used by the theoretical sciences was a tool ill-suited for discerning
answers sought by the practical sciences. In addressing particularly human
affairs, practitioners of the practical sciences had to settle for inexact
applications of inexact knowledge, in full awareness of the unpredictability
arising from human freedom and the variation of circumstances. Further, there
was an accompanying awareness that efforts to enforce political solutions drawn
from theoretical sciences were likely to end badly — as Aristotle intimates in
his criticisms of various utopian political schemes in Book II of the Politics, whether the communistic
family arrangements described by Plato in theRepublic, or the equalization of property defended by Phaleas of
Chalcedon, or the strict and mathematical division of social roles recommended
by Hippodamus of Miletus.
Thus, for
Aristotle, a science such as politics must rest in broad measure on observation
and human experience, but cannot be addressed through the approach employed by
the theoretical sciences. In turn, the theoretical sciences are thought to be
the highest and most godlike form of knowing, but do not offer a guide to
action. Ultimately, perhaps the most important kind of knowledge arising from
the practical sciences is the ability to maintain knowledge of the difference between the two
sciences. Maintaining this knowledge requires cultivating the habits of mind
and behavior necessary to avoid the temptation of applying one science in a
manner inappropriate to another, especially that temptation to apply a
theoretical solution to a problem arising from the phenomena examined by the
practical sciences. Part of exercising the judgment that arises especially from
the practical sciences, it was understood, was the ability to avoid applying
the theoretical approach to the human domain.
The Science
of Liberalism
Political
science — reflecting a certain approach to the knowledge of political matters
— was thus an appropriate undertaking so long as it employed the ancient
understanding of the word science.
But it would rest on the kinds of knowledge one would expect of the practical
sciences; history, rhetoric, warfare, economics, law, and other forms of
“practical” study were long understood to be necessary components in the study
of political phenomena. Parts of the “theoretical” sciences could be useful as
supplements to the study of political phenomena: for instance, a knowledge of
the behavior of rivers and a mastery of mathematics were helpful in planning
the construction of bridges. However, in such an approach, a distinction was
maintained between the two sciences as forms of comprehensive inquiry.
But the
advent of modernity was marked by the belief that political science could be
approached by the same method as the theoretical sciences. This transition
rested on two fundamental transformations — or, put another way, a kind of
inversion of the classical understanding of the role of the two sciences.
In the first
transformation, human beings came to be viewed as predictable material entities, governed by laws determining
their behavior. In particular, the philosophic efforts of Hobbes and later
Locke redefined human beings, understanding them to be subject to laws similar
in form to the Galilean laws of matter and motion, which determined human
activities and behaviors. Taking human beings to be motivated by fear, desire,
and, above all, self-interest, modern theorists dismissed the idea that virtues
could or ought to be the aim of politics. Rather, useful harnessing and
redirection of these motivations became the aim of the new science. By
understanding the universality and predictability of the laws of human
behavior, human beings could fashion structures of government that would no
longer be subject to the vagaries tolerated by and resulting from pre-modern political
science. The human sciences were to become forms of theoretical science.
In the
second transformation, natural phenomena were to be understood not as a subject of theoretical
study — that is, the object of contemplation — but rather, were to be understood
as material to be worked on, as a domain that could be altered and transformed
through human knowledge and activity. Action upon nature was to become the main
object of modern science, particularly as inaugurated by Francis Bacon. The
truly practical sciences
were now understood to be the natural sciences which would act upon nature,
altering its original form to exist in conformity with human comfort — to
provide for “the relief of man’s estate,” as Bacon put it.
While modern
political science was now understood to be subject to the same kinds of laws
that the ancients thought governed natural phenomena, the natural sciences were
now to be pursued in order to transform the subject of study, nature. The idea
that political principles operated according to ironclad laws lent itself to a
theory that was thought to be universally valid in all times and all places. At
the same time, nature was to be increasingly the subject of human dominion.
Human freedom was no longer seen as limited by nature, but was to be extended,
potentially infinitely, by the advance of modern science.
This
transformation, of course, describes the birth of liberalism — the philosophy
that sought to liberate humans from the constraints of a prior approach to
political philosophy that was content, in the words of Machiavelli, to settle
for “imagined republics and principalities.” It was in order to effect this end
that the revolution of the sciences first articulated by Francis Bacon and
Thomas Hobbes was embraced: To secure human liberty, political science must
become a theoretical science, while natural science must be treated as a
practical science, in the specific sense that it would be a realm of human
action and freedom. Within the horizon of a determined political setting — the
liberal state — human beings would achieve a form of security and a new kind of
liberty — the absence of constraint — through the conquest of nature.
Beyond
Liberal Science?
On the basis of a belief in the
fundamental predictability of human behavior, liberal theory laid claim to
universal legitimacy. But liberal theory, now only a few centuries old, may yet
prove historically short-lived, as we seem poised to enter into a new period of
scientific revolution. Early modern theory regarded human nature as fundamentally
“given” — in the same way that the ancients had regarded natural phenomena to
be “given” — while nature itself was regarded as fundamentally malleable. But
today we are confronted with a new understanding of humanity’s relationship to
nature, one deriving neither from the Aristotelian tradition, nor from
Hobbesian-Lockean theory, but from a logic inherent in Darwin’s discovery of
the mutability of nature.
While
Darwin’s theory itself, like Galileo’s observation of the heavens, takes the
form of ancient theoretical science (that is, the observation and contemplation
of natural phenomena), after its formulation, it too was quickly adapted to the
norms of the modern transformation of science, becoming “applied” in ways that
sought to make it comprehensive in its applicability. These efforts began,
infamously, as the late-nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century versions of
Social Darwinism, with corresponding efforts to apply what were thought to be
Darwinian approaches to the improvement of the species — particularly in the
form of eugenics: enforced infertility and the euthanizing of “inferior”
individuals and races. For all the viciousness of this attempted application of
Darwinism, these first translations of Darwin into a political science intuited
a basic implication of Darwin’s discovery: once Darwin articulated the basic
functioning of evolution, evolution in the form he described had officially
come to an end.
Indeed, as
the author Tom Wolfe pointed out in his 2006 Jefferson Lecture in the Humanities, as soon as humans developed
the ability of speech, they were effectively able to put an end to most forms
of accidental evolution. In developing the ability to dominate every other
species on the planet, humanity has taken charge of the evolutionary process.
It is not that evolution has ended: it is thataccidental evolution has ended (at least for the
foreseeable future), and instead, a new period of what is likely to be
conscious and planned evolution has taken its place.
The logic of
Darwinism suggests that once humans grasp the concept of evolution, humanity is
now in a position to assume responsibility for its own evolutionary development
and improvement. Where the early modern political thought that gave rise to
liberalism held that human nature is “given” and natural phenomena are mutable,
today we are increasingly likely to hold that everything is mutable in the hands of science — nature and
humanity alike. Thus enter the transhumanists. Author Simon Young, in Designer Evolution: A Transhumanist
Manifesto (2005), pens a letter to Nature itself in which he declares “our
intention to take over the business of Evolution.” He favorably quotes the
novelist William Gibson, who observed that “here we are, the first species
that’s ever effectively taken over its own evolution,” and claims that “we’re
going to change big time. It’s like human evolution is now designer evolution.”
Joel
Garreau, in his 2005 book Radical Evolution, has described what we might
expect to see through future “enhancements.” These include some relating to our
physical nature, such as longevity, accelerated healing, and greater beauty;
but also changes to our psyches, including heightened cognitive abilities,
photographic memory, total recall, “vaccination” against pain, the elimination
of sleep, wireless delivery of information directly to the brain, and even
electronically interconnected consciousness — and thus a wholly transformed
experience of selfhood. As Garreau giddily declares, we are in the midst of
“transforming no less than human nature.”
Scientific
revolutions, it should by now be clear, have not been limited to “science,” but
expand to underlying assumptions about the relationship of humanity to the
natural world, assumptions that inform our deepest political beliefs. The
revolution in scientific thinking in the early modern period, in which the
conquest of nature became a central aim, underlay the deepest presuppositions
of the liberal political project — just as a different scientific conception
had underlain the pre-modern understanding of politics, as aimed at realizing
the human telos.
Scientific assumptions unavoidably inform political theory.
And so we
can surmise that the expansion of the ideal of conquering nature to include
humanity itself is likely to have political consequences as far-reaching as the
scientific revolution that informed the now-nearly-universal modern regime of
liberalism. We can and must expect that a similar transformation of our
political ideas will come with what many hope to be the expansion of the
evolutionary imperative as knowingly and intentionally guided by scientific
advances and human design.
Despite the
historical parallel, experience offers us little guidance in the current
circumstance. For this newest scientific revolution begins with the rejection of the idea of any
immutable nature, whether the natural world or human nature itself. We find
ourselves in uncharted waters — an unknown topography that encourages
speculation about the future, pointing alternatively to nirvana and dystopia.
And the problem with either the dream or nightmare scenario, or anything in
between, is that our projections about the future are based upon contemporary, which is to
say steady, assumptions about human nature. But if the science proves to be
correct — if the transhumanist project really does succeed in remaking our
nature — then we are talking about a subject (post-human nature) with which we as yet do not have any
knowledge or experience. Speculations of any kind about such a future must then
be suspect.
In the cases
of the two broad political-scientific philosophies we can roughly call
Aristotelian and Lockean, we can see with some clarity the relationship between
the scientific assumptions and the political assumptions. In the pre-modern
view, human beings organized society around the ideal of attaining the virtues,
in light of the need to attain a proper condition of human freedom. Human
freedom was considered to be a condition of self-governance within self-imposed
limits, consistent with the idea of a given human nature and a fundamentally
unalterable natural order. While regime types varied in the pre-modern world, a
basic set of anthropological assumptions informed a broad consensus that
political society should be organized around the ideal of the attainment of
human virtues in accordance with a given human telos.
Early modern
thought rejected these assumptions, seeking to base political society upon
reliable and replicable scientific laws of human behavior (above all, the
reliability of self-interest and the fear of death as wellsprings of human
action), and to render those behaviors productive and beneficial by directing
them away from conflict in the political sphere and toward an expansion of
humanity’s capacity to exercise mastery over nature. Ancient limits upon
acquisitiveness were lifted, in the belief that the expansion of human mastery
could provide for the fulfillment of limitless human desires. Restlessness —
described so well by Tocqueville, though also anticipated by such thinkers as
Locke, Pascal, Rousseau, and Montesquieu — was predicted to become a basic
condition of modern life for every citizen.
The aspect
of these political ideas crucial for us moderns to note is that both were
premised upon the belief in some fixed human
nature, and the respective political beliefs and arrangements flowed from those
assumptions. That is, each political theory flowed in a sensible fashion from
basic aspects of human nature. Based upon observable facts of human behavior,
each respective political philosophy was able to articulate its essential
features by means of appeal to a certain fund of knowledge about humanity.
A
fundamental debate between ancients and moderns revolves around the question
of whichconception of human
nature is more correct — one oriented toward the attainment of virtue within a
fixed natural order, or one based upon the expansion of satisfactions of human
self-interest through the conquest of nature. In both cases, experience is
brought to bear: On the side of the ancients, contemporary authors such as
Alasdair MacIntyre argue that modern liberal philosophy and practice is not
only morally incoherent, but that it is destructive of the human soul, while
authors such as Wendell Berry additionally argue that the practical
consequences of the modern project make our world increasingly uninhabitable.
On the other side, defenders of liberalism point to its evident success on the
modern stage, especially the successes of science in pushing back an indifferent
and often cruel nature — thus, along with increasingly humane state policies,
increasing human health, wealth, and welfare. The move toward a neo-Darwinian
future invites us to consider these questions not only as they apply to the
modern project of nature’s dominion, but to the mastery of human biology
itself.
If we are at the advent of a new scientific order, then we must ask what political implications flow from a scientific revolution that urges the transformation of humanity itself. If the human race is to be altered in a unpredictable and perhaps fundamental manner, can any political arrangements or assumptions reliably flow from such a moving and unpredictable target?
If we are at the advent of a new scientific order, then we must ask what political implications flow from a scientific revolution that urges the transformation of humanity itself. If the human race is to be altered in a unpredictable and perhaps fundamental manner, can any political arrangements or assumptions reliably flow from such a moving and unpredictable target?
One common
set of concerns of critics on the left and the right about the transhumanist
project is the effectual division of human creatures into two separate groups —
“enhanced” and “naturals,” in the terminology of Joel Garreau, or “valids” and
“in-valids” in the terminology of the dystopian science-fiction film Gattaca. In response to these
concerns, libertarian-minded transhumanists seek to assure critics that
political solutions to such grim possibilities are sure to forestall any
fearful outcome. For instance, a “Frequently Asked Questions” document on the website of
the group Humanity+ (formerly known as the World Transhumanist Association, or
WTA) admits that
some
technologies may cause social inequalities to widen. For example, if some form
of intelligence amplification becomes available, it may at first be so
expensive that only the wealthiest can afford it. The same could happen when we
learn how to genetically enhance our children. Those who are already well off
would become smarter and make even more money.
However,
seeking to assuage those concerns, the guide continues:
Trying to
ban technological innovation on these grounds, however, would be misguided. If
a society judges existing inequalities to be unacceptable, a wiser remedy would
be progressive taxation and the provision of community-funded services such as
education, IT access in public libraries, genetic enhancements covered by
social security, and so forth. Economic and technological progress is not a
zero sum game; it’s a positive sum game. Technological progress does not solve
the hard old political problem of what degree of income redistribution is
desirable, but it can greatly increase the size of the pie that is to be
divided.
The guide
adds that such problems could also be averted by strengthening “those
institutions that prevent violence and protect human rights, for instance by
building stable democratic traditions and constitutions and by expanding the
rule of law to the international plane.” Commenting on this part of the document, James Hughes, the
self-described “democratic transhumanist,” claims that “the transhumanists are
anticipating the need to build political and cultural solidarity between humans
and post-humans, to minimize conflicts, and to have global police institutions
that can protect humans from post-humans and vice versa. In short, the WTA
documents establish a broad political tent, with an explicit embrace of
political engagement, the need to defend and extend liberal democracy, and the
inclusion of social democratic policy alternatives as legitimate points of
discussion.”
Addressing
another set of concerns, namely, the fear that — as in the past — a eugenics
policy may become the result of political fiat, enforced by a tyrant with the
goal of liquidating sub-par humans, Simon Young assures his readers: “In the
modern world, we do not live under totalitarian regimes, but in democracies, in
which individuals are free to do as they please so long as their actions do not
harm others. Superbiology will and must be controlled by individual consumers,
not the state. We should protect ourselves from totalitarianism by voting out
of office any government which shows the first signs of a drift toward authoritarianism.”
This all
sounds well and good — but on what basis can it be assumed that liberal
political institutions will remain relevant or applicable to a creature
that we do not yet know we will
become? What sense can we make of appeals to our “democratic traditions”
when those traditions rest on a fundamentally different set of anthropological
assumptions? Liberal forms and institutions are the consequence of a particular
scientific and political understanding, one that would be fundamentally altered
by a neo-Darwinian transformation. Unlike the ancient or modern views I’ve
described, this new understanding aims at the fundamental alteration of
humanity itself. How can it be predicted or assumed in advance that political
institutions and practices derived from a pre-transhumanist scientific and
political understanding will continue to apply or be regarded as relevant? Is
it not just as likely that our future selves will come to regard the liberal
regime as even more of an antiquated curiosity than we now regard the
city-state? For all of the futurism of the neo-Darwinians, when it comes to
their political assumptions, they reveal themselves to be utter nostalgists,
clinging to a provincial form of belief that is utterly unjustified and
unwarranted by their own scientific assumptions.
Neo-Darwinians
often resort to explaining our social condition as the result of a long process
of social evolution, which gave us the capacity to cooperate with strangers and
eventually to establish institutions and behaviors that permit increasingly
global forms of governance. Thus, Simon Young argues, “diversity and
cooperation have evolved because they increase our ability to survive.” The
confidence of various transhumanists in the ability of liberal institutions to
resist any authoritarian or inegalitarian outcomes arising from an enhancement
regime seems to derive from a belief in the continuation of this evolutionary
trend. But if humans are now going to actively alter our very composition, to
what extent can we have confidence that the institutions and processes that
have developed by a very different evolutionary track, for very different
creatures, will not be regarded as fundamentally disposable? Again, the
assumptions about a liberal future seem to be more a matter of faith than
science.
Finally,
further and deeper reflection on the sedimentation of our various political
traditions ought to give pause. The most thoughtful liberals — perhaps above
all, Tocqueville — recognized that liberalism contained an internal logic that
threatened its own self-destruction. The anthropological individualism at the
heart of its theory could be given institutional credence so long as those
assumptions did not colonize every aspect of human life. Liberalism rested
fundamentally on pre-modern and pre-liberal institutions and practices, ranging
from family to community, from church to civil society. In spite of the
official rejection of the pre-modern tradition, liberalism assumed and
benefited from a kind of “unofficial” continuity of the pre-modern,
Aristotelian-inflected inheritance. Thus, Tocqueville observed, though
Americans justified their actions in terms of self-interest, they continued to
act altruistically. He wrote that “they would rather do honor to their
philosophy than to themselves.”
The proposed
new scientific settlement would introduce an even thinner human anthropology.
In this view, humanity is reduced largely to physical bodies that seek life and
health. Families, where they make an appearance, are generally composed of parents
who seek to enhance their children. Society is envisioned as composed of
near-immortal autonomous individuals who pursue their own ends, forever.
Ironically
enough, transhumanism gains a great deal of its persuasive and intuitive force
from its reliance upon our widespread experience of self-sacrificial parental
love. We are asked, who would not want to prevent a child from being born with
a terrible disease? And what parents don’t want to give their children every
advantage in life, whether SAT preparation, or, if it comes to it, genetic
enhancement?
Yet the
motivation of transhumanism is finally selfish: each of us wants, or should
want, to live forever in a condition of perfect health and expanded faculties.
What then becomes of the relationship between the generations? In a world of
limited resources, space, and opportunity, would not the next generation now be
experienced as a threat? Would not every inclination cry out against
reproduction? Would not our experience of humanity as generational creatures,
bound ceaselessly in relationship to the past and to the future, cease to be a
fact of our existence?
Liberalism
was the first major step in the weakening of our generational consciousness. As
conceived by the theorists of the “state of nature,” humans are to be
conceived by nature as
autonomous, parentless, childless creatures. Society is the consequence of
voluntary choice aimed at mutual advantage, not reciprocal gratitude and
inherited obligations. Yet this theory was always leavened by the fact of our pre-modern
inheritance. Families, communities, and religion, even if weakened by the
forces and logic of modern liberalism, even if puttering along in bold though
largely unrealized defiance of the theories that purport to dispose of them, nevertheless
have long persisted as a bulwark against the full implication of liberal
theory.
The
looming new scientific
settlement of neo-Darwinism intimates a final conclusion to this tenuous
relationship between ancient and modern political science, proposing a new
creature oriented entirely around the satisfactions of a new, enhanced,
near-perfect, near-immortal self. If liberal theory has shown itself to be
largely incapable of thinking in generational terms, encouraging a populace
that demands immediate gratification at the cost of the solvency of future
generations, and promoting an ethic of consumption with no mind to the
challenges posed to the planet for the unborn, then what of our transhumanist
future and the prospects for generational hostility? The unknowability of the
nature of a post-human being precludes us from drawing any firm conclusion
about what its future will be like. But drawing upon lessons ancient and
modern, and looking at the impulses that lead us to want to make ourselves into
beings that are not ourselves, it seems that our transhumanist future portends
to be anything but humane.
No comments:
Post a Comment