The motor of human
history turns on the question of political form. In the ancient world, two such
forms prevailed: the city-state and the empire. Indeed, the history of the
ancient world is essentially the history of the interplay of these two forms,
whether through war (as in the Greek cities’ war against the Persian Empire) or
through a city’s becoming an empire. Athens was an imperialistic city, but it
didn’t succeed in becoming—or at least in maintaining—an empire. It was
Alexander, who came from the periphery of the Greek world, who established the
Greek empire. From then on, an imperial Greek space existed that was soon
occupied by a newcomer: Rome, which made the almost unbelievable effort of
transforming itself from a little city into a world empire (see “City, Empire, Church,
Nation,” Summer 2012).
These are
elementary historical facts, and yet, on close inspection, they reveal a
remarkable intelligibility. The city is the smallest human association capable
of self-government, while the empire is the most extensive possible grouping
under a single sovereign. Thus we have two conceptions of humanity, two ways of
crystallizing the fact of being human. Not only might we say that the ancient
order was based on these two great political forms and their interrelations; we
might add that this ancient order was the “natural” order of human things, as
both forms developed spontaneously, without any previous idea or
conception—unlike the modern state.
The persistence of
empire in European history after the fall of Rome is striking: the Holy Roman
Empire, the French Empire, the German Empire, and now the European Union, which
some call an empire. Yet empires didn’t determine the form of Europe. Nor was European
life organized mainly in city-states, though the city saw some remarkable
developments in such places as Italy, Flanders, and the Rhineland. Why did
Europe gradually abandon the two natural forms of human association? And why
did a third form, for which there was no equivalent in the ancient world,
finally prevail?
To understand the
modern nation’s displacement of the ancient city and empire, one should start
with Cicero, who was the first to confront the problem of the city’s viability
and of its passage into another political form. Trained in Greek philosophy,
Cicero had learned and accepted the classical interpretation of the republican
government under which he lived: the notion that the best regime was a mixture
of monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy. But that framework no longer made
sense in the context of a Rome that was stretching beyond the limits of the
city. Cicero was thus caught between old notions—in fact, notions that he had
undertaken to explain to his compatriots—and the rise of something new. For
something unprecedented was happening in Rome: for the first time, a city, the
most compact and dense political form, was expanding in an effort to encompass
the whole world. Herein lay a challenge for thought and for political action.
As for action,
Cicero, of course, lost his life in that effort. But what especially interests
us is the way he tried to adapt old categories to a new world. A careful
reading of Cicero’s political works shows that they subject Greek philosophy to
a profound transformation and contain certain doctrines or themes that we
associate with modern political philosophy. One example of these innovations is
that Cicero defines the magistrate as the “bearer of the public person.” But
this notion of the public person—as abstracted at once from the particular
judgment of the magistrate and from any immediate choice on the part of the
citizen body—was unknown to the Greek city. Another example: his statement that
the protection of property is the function of the political order—again, a
foreign concept to the Greeks. A third: Cicero emphasizes the particularity of
each person, distinguishing between the nature common to human beings and the
nature proper to an individual person; he invites the individual not only to
follow nature, as Greek philosophy would have it, but to follow his own nature.
These elements
imply a profound reconsideration of Greek political philosophy, one that
attempts to account for a new situation by using new terms. An emphasis on
one’s particular nature obviously gives that nature increased authority in the
public space. The definition of political order in terms of the protection of
property brings private affairs to a new position of prominence—again, at the
expense of the public space. Finally, the political realm loses the real,
substantial character that it had when the city was visible as a whole that
could be seen all at once; now that the city is so extensive, it is the
magistrate who shines forth in the public light.
All these
innovations suggest that Cicero took note of and encouraged, to some degree,
the decomposition and recomposition of the civic political order and that he
was sketching the main features of a new order, even if its elements weren’t
sufficient on their own to constitute that order. That is, they didn’t succeed
in preserving civic life—what Machiavelli later called the vivere
civile or vivere politico—in a political form that was no
longer the city. The indeterminacy of Cicero’s thought is particularly evident
in The Republic, which moves in two opposite directions: on the one
hand, it emphasizes the collective wisdom of the Romans throughout the course
of their history, thus playing down the importance of individual legislators;
on the other hand, it seeks a royal figure, a princeps capable
of restoring the civic order that the mixed regime, though inherently
preferable, has proved incapable of preserving.
Over the course of
the next 15 centuries, Cicero remained the person who had most intelligently
gathered together the usable elements of the ancient political tradition. He
was a major reference for Saint Augustine, as for Thomas Aquinas. His
authority, during the centuries that we call Christian, was roughly equal to
that of the church fathers. He was truly the source of political
thought. And those centuries, which preceded the formation of the modern order
and the construction of the modern state, were characterized by the absence or
indeterminacy of the political order. Neither empire nor city was able to meet
the requirements of the time. We can call this long period of indeterminacy the
“Ciceronian moment.”
It’s hard to know
what to make of the period. We may know a lot about it, but we aren’t able to
discern a coherent human order in it. We have a coherent picture of the ancient
order—the Greek and then the Roman order—insofar as we find there a coherent
civic life. We have a still more complete comprehension of the modern order, in
that the modern state is constructed on a plan that can be called
philosophical. There are thus two long periods of intelligibility. If we read
histories of political philosophy, we find in them the great body of ancient
thought and the great body of modern thought—and a long period between the two,
concerning which we don’t know what to say. Thanks to the division of labor in
universities, you can easily locate fine scholarly volumes devoted to medieval
political thought. But if you look into the subject, you’ll realize that
medieval authors’ thinking is essentially divided between those who carry on
the ancient tradition and those who announce or prepare the work of the
moderns. True, the Middle Ages have been “rehabilitated” in the academy. But
our recognition of the period’s accomplishments shouldn’t distract us from what
is decisive from a political perspective: the human world during those
centuries doesn’t lend itself to our comprehension because it had no experience
of an adequately coherent human order.
Indeed, to
understand the Middle Ages, one must pay attention to the absence or indeterminacy
of the political order. Throughout those centuries, Europe was in search of
such an order. The disorder of European politics and the effort to find a way
out of it—the desire and the need for a reasonable and coherent political
order—was the cause of European development. The root historical cause was the
desire of human beings to be well governed, or at least not too badly governed.
What drove history was man’s political
nature.
It thus becomes
clear that modernity was defined by a movement toward a reordering. Medieval
authors were unable to find this principle of order, despite the “holism” said
to have prevailed in that age. Rather, they were caught up for ten centuries in
a plethora of approximate and not necessarily compatible references, including
small or large doses of Aristotle, a lot of Cicero, a bit of the church
fathers, a few references from the Bible, and some Latin historians—and all
this was supposed to provide the basis of a coherent doctrine. But no such
doctrine would be elaborated until the seventeenth century, when, after the
sixteenth-century rupture associated with Machiavelli and with Luther, it
finally became possible to make a fresh start.
The universal human
need for order or good government operated in Europe in a framework defined by
two conditions. The first, as we’ve seen, was the experience of the Ciceronian
moment—the difficulty or impossibility of recovering the lost civic life of the
ancients. The second was the Christian proposition of a human community at once
broader and narrower than any political community, a proposition that couldn’t
help but question the legitimacy of the two great ancient political forms of
city and empire.
It was Machiavelli
who responded most audaciously to the situation. But what exactly was his
project? What political form, old or new, did he draw upon—the city, the
empire, perhaps a new nation along the lines of the strong French monarchy
beginning to emerge? The answer isn’t clear. What is certain, though, is that
he conceived of action as still possible, a striking alternative to the inertia
of the Ciceronian moment. Consider simply his idea of the virtuous prince—the
prince endowed with a virtue that consists of the capacity to oppose and to
master fortune. Or consider Machiavelli’s tone, constantly suggesting that we
must not let anything discourage us; or his statement that fortune favors the
audacious.
But Machiavelli
didn’t clearly outline the new order that action was supposed to produce. He
did define a certain number of conditions of that action, famously dismissing
all moral or religious precepts, all prudential maxims, and all forms of
respect transmitted with our mothers’ milk that might forbid, fetter, or
discourage action. He replaced the maxims of morality with his own maxims, which
were so intentionally shocking as to wake men up to their passivity and to the
inertia induced by the action-shackling idea of the good. His ideas didn’t form
recognizable political institutions; they were to institutional construction
what the preparation of artillery is to battle. In this way, Machiavelli
provided the conditions of the possibility of a new order. The new order
required that Europeans believe in the possibility of creative and founding
action—that they believe that it was time to forget the old Greek, Roman, and
Christian foundations in favor of new ones.
If Machiavelli
were a theologian, one might say that he reduced all the theological virtues to
one: hope. If he were a moral philosopher, one might likewise say that he
reduced all the cardinal virtues to one: courage. Of course, he was neither.
What he preached was a new political action—a radical, unprecedented,
transformative, founding action—and he preached it in the absence of any
available, or even prospective, political order. The order remained
indeterminate; but with Machiavelli, we hear—for the first time in Europe—the
call to revolution.
The role of the
Protestant Reformation in the emergence of the new order becomes clear as we
consider that it presented itself directly and explicitly as a political
movement. The heart of the Reformation was undeniably its attack on the
mediating character of the Catholic Church. The Church saw itself as the
necessary vehicle for salvation and as the mediator between man and God. Luther
directly and violently attacked that claim, and the ensuing destruction of
ecclesiastical mediation brought about profound political disruptions.
For one thing, the
rupture of ecclesiastical mediation gave power, including spiritual power, to
the temporal prince, since it stripped spiritual princes—the Church and its
prelates—of their legitimacy. The repository of religious authority was
henceforth the community of citizens (if one can speak of citizens at this
point) or the community of believers; and since those communities were governed
by temporal princes, it was these princes who inherited the mediating power.
A second political
consequence of the Reformation: if the spiritual community, the Christian
community, wasn’t the universal Catholic Church, it followed that it was the
community as defined politically and temporally. Now, the community as defined
politically and temporally was the national community. So the Lutheran
Reformation was, to a large extent, a national revolution—a German revolution,
for which Germans long afterward felt nostalgia.
The breakdown of
Catholic mediation, in other words, contributed to the reinforcement of two
elements that proved decisive in the constitution of modern Europe: the
sovereignty of temporal princes and the authority of the national principle. We
will never know what Machiavelli would have thought of the Reformation’s
political consequences. But it certainly contributed to the destruction of an
inertia that he deplored: the political impunity of spiritual princes. The end
of Catholic mediation was a necessary precondition for an active rapprochement
between temporal princes and Christian peoples.
The Catholic
Church, too, had been a brake on human action; it tended to dissuade the
faithful from undertaking action in this world. But now, with the Church set
aside, the elements of the social world accelerated. Secular institutions, such
as work and marriage, were freed from competition with spiritual
institutions—namely, the monastic orders and consecrated celibacy. To understand
the effects of the Reformation on human action, there is no need to resort to
Max Weber’s ingenious but obscure theses on the economic effects of the
doctrine of predestination. Insofar as religion was a factor, what was
essential for the acceleration of movement was the destruction of the Church’s
braking mediation.
Simplicity is
desirable in historical explanation. Just as my interpretation of what I have
called the Ciceronian moment presupposes nothing more than the simple
proposition that people prefer being governed well to being governed badly, so
my interpretation of the Reformation rests on the simple proposition that the
relation between humanity and divinity—whether divinity exists or not—carries
with it the question of mediation. The relation between humanity and divinity
unfolds in two opposite directions: on the one hand, we seek a correct idea, a
worthy and adequate idea, of divinity, and so we hold the divine as far apart
from humanity as possible; we thus speak of divine transcendence. On the other
hand, we necessarily wish to enter into a relationship with this transcendent
God; that is, we seek mediation.
And when we study
the past, we must always link historical causality with nonhistorical
causality—that is, with something that belongs not to the condition of the
Greeks or Romans or Christians or moderns, but to the human condition. Just as
the human condition includes the problem of governing, it includes a connection
to the divine and thus to the problem of mediating divinity. These simple
issues, inherent in the human condition, should frame our efforts to comprehend
any age, including our own.
The Ciceronian
moment ended with the period, prepared by Machiavelli and facilitated by the
Protestant Reformation, when the form of the nation crystallized victoriously
and came to be considered the natural framework of civilized human life. There
is no doubt that Europeans of all nationalities, at the end of the nineteenth
and beginning of the twentieth centuries, felt that they inhabited the most
perfectly developed political form.
In Europe, at
least, that idea has since grown foreign. During the twentieth century, the
nation-state was discredited and is now increasingly regarded as a type of
human association that belongs to a past age. Europeans have therefore
undertaken to build a new political form—or rather, let’s say that they have
assumed the perspective in which they envisage a new political form called
“Europe.” Europeans still belong to the old nation, and yet they see themselves
as one day belonging to a Europe—indeed, a Europe that already constitutes a
part of their experience, though in an extremely limited and artificial way.
Like Cicero, they find themselves at a point of transition from one type of
human association to another—and they will not be governed well until they face
the question that is once again thrust upon them: the question of political
form.
No comments:
Post a Comment