Part I. Sociobiology and Social Engineering
By Pedro Schwartz
Democracy is an unstable
system that often does disservice to individual liberty. With this stark
assertion I want to pose two problems that have been with the friends of
democracy from the very earliest times—going back to the Athenian followers of
Pericles when traduced by Plato, to Alexis de Tocqueville and John Stuart Mill when concerned with the
enlargement of the franchise, down to Friedrich Hayek and James Buchanan when proposing remedies
for the demagoguery of our day. The first is that government of the people, by
the people, for the people has more than once been on the point of perishing
from the Earth. The second is that democracy, though the political corollary of
individualism, has in practice often tyrannized the individual. One explanation
for the recurring instability and frequent oppressiveness of democratic
politics is that they are due to the natural attrition of human arrangements. A
better answer is that they are the consequence of systematic flaws in our
political systems. Democracy as practiced is flawed. Democratic life is beset
by paradox. These imperfections must be brought into the open and remedied if
we want liberal democracy to survive.
Let me give two samples of the
confusion and contradiction that beset present day political life: the crisis
of Welfare and the denial of capitalist growth.
The failure of the Welfare
State
The financial crisis that
started in 2007 is perceived in Europe as the writing on the wall for the
original idea of the Welfare State. Financing pensions, health, and education
on egalitarian lines is now seen as a system of social service with all the
wrong incentives: demand runs wild, quality of service deteriorates and taxpayers
groan under their weight.
The trouble is that a majority
of voters seem to want a Welfare State that they now know is unsustainable. For
many years they were content to sell their birthright for a mess of potage but
suddenly now they fear they will go hungry: their pensions are being cut, the
queues before the hospitals grow longer, and an increasing number of their
young go uneducated.
These troubles do not affect
Europeans only. In the United States, public opinion is divided regarding the
unstoppable growth of Government debt. The need to reduce the deficit of the
Federal Treasury is widely acknowledged, though there is disagreement about the
speed of the consolidation. There is even a plan in the United States to extend
entitlements along the lines of the failed European experiment. This does not
stop a majority from wanting to put new debt-financed programs in train, be
they as expensive as so-called Obamacare. When the minority tries to resist
lifting the debt ceiling to fund such new entitlements, the Federal Government
is able to bring public opinion on its side by showing that new debt is needed
to cover ordinary expenses such as military pensions or civil servants
salaries: the world turned upside down.
People love to hate the market
The hostility to the market
always present in democratic politics has become acute with the 2007-2011
financial crisis. How acute can be gauged by the general denial of the positive
effects of globalization on poverty. The commonplace assertion is that the
expansion of capitalism is making the poor poorer and the rich richer all
around the world. This is contrary to fact. If poverty is defined in absolute
terms as the state of people living below a certain threshold of consumption,
then the story of globalization in the last thirty years is astoundingly
positive. In an academic article crowning a long effort to measure world
poverty, Xavier Sala-i-Martin, with the help of Maxim Pinkovskiy (2009)1 , shows that, if the poverty threshold is
defined as living below $1 a day, "the total number of poor thus defined
has fallen from 403 million in 1970 to 152 million in 2006"—a reduction of
251 million poor in thirty-six years. The same trend is revealed for higher
thresholds of poverty. That figure is especially telling since the data have
been observed in the midst of a growing world population, which should have led
to an increase in the number of poor. It cannot be a mere coincidence that
those years have been marked by a steady expansion of international trade and
foreign direct investment, in other words, by increasing globalization.2 Time has proved Milton and Rose Friedman right when in Capitalism
and Freedom (1962, 2002) they pointed at capitalism to explain the
prosperity of the free part of the world. Globalization is the spread of
liberty and the story of economic freedom is one of falling poverty and
inequality, together with a marked progress in welfare.
Despite these observable
facts, intellectual opinion and political belief go the other way. Religious
leaders, intellectual elites and ordinary people ceaselessly denounce the
worsening state of the poor and root for political intervention to control the
free market, precisely the institution that makes for the reduction of poverty
and the increase in wellbeing.
Why such deliberate blindness
to the benefits of economic freedom enjoyed by growing numbers around the
world? Again it seems that this is more than a passing fad or a mere
coincidence. It shows that liberal democracy suffers from a deep contradiction:
people are discontent with our societies while they expect and demand boundless
improvement from their progress.
The politics of market control
This contradiction between
opinion and behavior often turn democrats into collectivists, because it
fosters mistrust of trade, rejection of competition, fear of price changes,
aversion to new wealth, in short, general suspicion of the free market. This leads
to democracy being proposed as a system to control spontaneous social change
politically, rather than as a system to transmit individual choices. When later
voters notice the corruption implicit in political log-rolling or in the
sharing out of 'pork' this view of democracy leads to, they pine for more
republican politics where politicians look for the common good, whatever that
may be.
Economic competition is based
on free agreements for mutual gain; politics (and politically governed markets)
are about extracting rents. I shall have something to say later in these three
columns about the fundamental distinction between the positive-sum games of the
free market and the negative-sum games of rent seeking, a distinction that
ordinary voters find difficult to make.
Four paradoxes of modern
democracy
Ailments such as those
evidenced in the above two examples are no accident or mere coincidence. Their
causes may be concealed but they still bear witness to deep contradictions in
democratic life and practice.
There are many sources of
paradox in our democracies. I will turn my attention to four, which I want to
deal with in this and the next few essays.
1. The first one is that the ideals of individualism and citizenship may be
discounted as not fully in harmony with our human nature; in fact, they may be
rejected as not natural at all.
2. The democratic vote may result in communal decisions that nobody wants,
as coming at the expense of personal preferences; the nation, though the
natural venue for popular sovereignty, may often be the source of stifling
tribalism.
3. Thirdly, the confusion of wealth with freedom and poverty with serfdom
will tempt many to portray formal liberties as an in-egalitarian sham.
4. And last, money, which Hayek saw as 'one of the greatest instruments of
freedom ever invented by man', repeatedly suffers from financial disorders that
endanger liberty, as the crises of the 1930s and the first decade of the
present century show.
The paradox of the liar
It is my view that these four
contradictions are not incurable. They are in the character of semantic loops
one encounters in ordinary discourse and in computer programs. These loops can
be solved by separating planes of meaning, so that self-reference is avoided.
One of the oldest is the "paradox of the Liar", which runs thus:
"Epimenides the Cretan says that all Cretans are liars."
Many authors solve this
contradiction by separating levels of propositions, even visibly with inverted
commas, thus:
"Epimenides, the Cretan says: 'all Cretans are liars'."
This sentence is true if in
fact Epimenides said as much, whether he was contradicting himself or not.
Each of these four paradoxes
of democratic life suffers from a self-reference that has to be cut so that
they escape the vicious circle that afflicts them. This is done by moving the
discourse to a 'meta-plane'. Let me explain this perhaps obscure expression
taken from the discussion of semantic paradoxes at the beginning of the 20th
century.3 The solution just proposed for the Liar paradox
consists in separating the miscreant proposition into two parts: one within the
single marks, couched in what is technically called the 'object language'; and
the rest expressed in what is called the 'meta-language'. The meta-language
sentence passes judgment on the object sentence and by excluding self-reference
avoids the paradox.
The four paradoxes of liberal
democracy that I want to discuss in these columns belong to the same class of
semantic paradoxes as that of the Liar.
1. If the modern economy is seen as unnatural or irrational because it
breaks with tradition or has not been politically designed, then it will be
rejected as undemocratic, though it is the result of the free actions of
innumerable individuals.
2. If whatever the majority decides is right then majoritarian democracy
can vote itself out of existence.
3. If liberal democracy is based on the principle that all men are equal,
then the free market, based on the principle of free individual choice, will be
rejected as leading to undemocratic inequality.
4. If by democratic decision money starts to be issued in excess, then its
role as a symbol of value may be fundamentally undermined.
Semantic paradoxes are not
mere logical curios. They often become 'existential', in that they embody a
shocking or absurd trait of reality. Living with such paradoxes becomes
unbearable. Solving them becomes a way to approach the truth. Hence, the very
evolution of social life leads to habits or institutions appearing on a
meta-plane that help societies escape such vicious circles.
The object of this column and
the next ones is to sketch ways to free democratic life of deformities such as
the ones listed here. The object is to make democracy more amicable to
individual freedom. I shall explore solutions to the four paradoxes based on
creating or cultivating meta-planes of meaning to solve deadly contradictions,
along the following lines.
1. Our personal instincts as to what is natural should not lead us to
disallow unpredictable social evolution on a higher plane because its results
feel artificial.
2. People who use their democratic rights to destroy liberal democracy
should not necessarily be given full leeway but be made to abide by the higher
rules of a Constitution.
3. The equality demanded by democrats should be limited to equality
before the law by a meta-rule.
4. Money creation should be anchored by some well-grounded meta-rule so
that credit does not grow excessively by feeding on itself.
I shall note in the conclusion
of these essays that ladders onto higher planes allowing democracies to escape
from vicious circles tend to develop spontaneously with economic growth and
cultural progress. With the passage of time, institutional fire-walls tend to
appear that break the loops of democratic life. History shows that people can learn
to be democratic in ways that are not inimical to personal freedom.
I. THE ERRORS OF BIOLOGICAL
DETERMINISM AND SOCIAL ENGINEERING
Freud on culture as unnatural repression
Freud on culture as unnatural repression
Late in life, Sigmund Freud
published one of his most striking essays, Civilization and its
Discontents. 4 I am not the only one to have felt when
reading this work that Freud was still under the impression of the cruelty of
World War I and the harshness of its aftermath when thus taking stock of human
culture in 1930. The legend has it that, when sailing into New York for the
first time in 1909 he turned to Jung at his side and said, "They don't
realize that we are bringing the plague".5 The plague was the spreading of the belief
that civilized repression was to be exorcised if mankind would be rid of its
unhappiness. Was he perhaps ruining the day when he let loose the devils of the
libido and blamed repression for the neuroses of mankind?
Man's discontent goes deep,
says Freud. Humans are perpetually faced with the omnipotence of destiny and
the futility of their own striving. In childhood they crucially depend on
others and are naturally open to the religious impulse. Their anguish is
prolonged in adult years by the unavoidable presence of three sources of human
suffering: the supremacy of Nature, the decay of our own body, and deficient
human relations in the family, society and the state. The latter are especially
painful since we devised those institutions, he says, for our happiness,
welfare and protection. Freud was thus questioning even the benefits of
arrangements purposely devised by thinking men.
All this, however, does not
explain "the strange hostility of so many men against culture". For
Freud, a second cause could be found in our disappointment with the technical
advances of the age.
In the course of the last
generations, humanity has realized extraordinary progress in the natural
sciences and their technical applications. [... ] Man is justly proud of such
conquests but has begun to suspect that these recently acquired powers [... ]
have not made him happier.
Freud coined a cruel
expression to describe the continuous dissatisfaction of humans despite
extraordinary increases in the power of technology:
Man, so to speak, has come to
be a god with artificial limbs, magnificent enough [... when he dons] his
prostheses but these do not grow from his body and sometimes cause him
considerable distress.
A god with prostheses! Such
was the second step in his diagnosis of man's hostility towards culture.
Freud wanted to go deeper,
however, in his explanation of the discontents of civilization. The third and
more fundamental cause was that man's sexuality and aggressive instincts were
savage and violent and had to be repressed for social life to be possible.
Whoever remembers the horrors
of the great migrations, the invasions of the Huns, of the moguls under Genghis
Khan and Tamerlane, the conquest of Jerusalem by the pious crusaders, and even
the cruelties of the last World War must humbly accept the reality [of human
aggressiveness].
The necessary repression gave
rise to the neurosis of civilized man, who often relieved it by reverting to
blind participation in communal life. The aggressive tendencies of mankind could
be channeled in defense of the tribe. These small groups had
... the very appreciable advantage of permitting the satisfaction of instinct through the hostility against outsiders [... ] thus easing the cohesion of the members of the community.
Echoes of Thomas Hobbes in his
extoling of social repression: man was freest before culture, but this natural
liberty "had no value because the individual was barely capable of
defending it", was Freud's conclusion. It went in the same direction as Hobbes:
free institutions were not in harmony with man's primordial nature.
Hayek's three sources of
sociability.
The Freudian idea that the
institutions of the free society inevitably clashed with the true nature of man
was subtly changed by Hayek. The text to be read and reread in this regard is
his pithy "Epilogue" to Law, Legislation and Liberty,6 titled "The three sources of human
values" (1982). It is there Hayek rejected the general view that human
institutions were either of biological or of rational origin.
Culture is neither natural nor artificial, neither genetically transmitted nor rationally designed. [... ] The structures formed by traditional human practices are neither natural in the strict sense of being genetically determined, nor artificial in the sense of being the product of intelligent design. (Hayek, page 155)
First, he did accept that
"man has been civilized much against his wishes" and that there was
discontent in our civilization due to a feeling of helplessness of individual
men and women to control the forces that shape their lives.
Secondly, he did not rest
content with Freud's classification of the sources of civilized discontent into
neurotic repression and technical artifice. Even in closed societies of a
primitive kind there was control and invention, but these were accepted and
welcomed. There was another source of discontent that was felt as impersonal
and often sinister. The institutions of civilized life evolved spontaneously
through purblind competition. They were opaque and even incomprehensible to the
individual.
These new rules were not supported by the awareness that they were more effective. We have never defined our economic system. We were not intelligent enough for that. We have stumbled into it, has carried us to unforeseen heights and given rise to ambitions which may yet lead us to destroy it. (page 164)
Thirdly, Hayek did not deplore
the emergence of rules that disciplined human nature, much to the contrary:
"Freedom was made possible by the gradual evolution of the discipline of civilization which is at the same time the discipline of freedom"(page 163).
This is what led Hayek to say that
"the morals which maintain the open society do not serve to gratify human emotions" (page 160).
The reason why many institutions of the modern world
are misunderstood or indeed rejected by modern man is that indeed they are not
'natural', nor are they 'rational' in the sense of being consciously devised
for a defined purpose.
One must remember that one of
the reasons why Hayek wrote this Epilogue was to correct "the errors of
sociobiology". For Hayek, that school was mistaken in believing that the
customs and the institutions of human beings could be 'reduced' to their
genetic nature, that is to say, biologically deconstructed. Also, one must not
forget that the purpose of Volume I of Law, Legislation, and Liberty,
titled "Rules and Order" was to reject what he called
'constructivism,' the belief that it was rational and possible to design
institutions from scratch as if they were the artificial limbs Freud so
tellingly described. In sum, the principle on which Hayek based his analysis of
institutions was that encapsulated in Adam Ferguson's famous phrase that
"nations stumble upon establishments, which are indeed the result of human action, but not the execution of any human design."7
All this means that humans do
not fully understand the nature and effects of the institutions of civilized life
and that attempts to order them from top to bottom are nugatory. The evolution
of the economic order in the progress of our civilization goes very much
against the grain of the customs and beliefs of the tribal life we have only
partially outgrown. Neither does it conform to the demands of Cartesian logic.
[... F]rom the toleration of bartering with the outsider, the recognition of delimited private property, especially in land, the enforcement of contractual obligations, the competition with fellow craftsmen in the same trade, the variability of initially customary prices, the lending of money, particularly at interest, were all initially infringements of customary rules. (page 161)
We live in anguish (or
discontent, as Freud would have said) because the rules which "maintain
the open society do not serve to gratify human emotions".
The basic tools of civilization—language, morals, law, and money—are the result of spontaneous growth and not of design, and of the last two organized power has got hold and thoroughly corrupted them. (page 163)
Popper and the abstract
society 8
All this Karl Popper had
stressed many years before. When discussing Plato's reactionary philosophy in
his The Open Society and its Enemies (1945, 1957) he came to
the, for him, surprising conclusion that Plato was right in saying that the
ancient Greeks "were suffering under a severe strain, and that strain was
due to the social revolution which had begun with the rise of democracy and
individualism." (1957, page 171). Life in the tribe accords better with
our inherited traits. When society moves away from functioning like an organism
the result can be unsettling.
An open society may become, by
degrees, what I should like to term an 'abstract society'.[... ] We could
conceive of a society in which men practically never meet face to face—in which
all business is conducted by individuals in isolation who communicate by typed
letters or telegrams, and who go about in closed motor-cars.
True, Popper had added that
relationships, which in a closed society were set by accident of birth or place
in social hierarchy, changed in an open society to becoming personal objects of
choice. But, as Popper concluded,
[A]lthough society has become abstract, the biological make-up of man has not changed much; men have social needs which they cannot satisfy in an abstract society. (pages 174-175)
The moral rejection of
efficient markets
The instinctive rejection of
the ethics of the Open Society has an unexpected effect: it leads ordinary
people to fret against the conclusions of economics even when they are well
established and tested. This makes the life of the classical economist a
frustrating experience. Our science of economics seems to oppose the fond
beliefs and moral principles of ordinary people, so that markets go unloved and
suffer continuous interference.
In a recent clear-sighted
essay, Clark and Lee9underline the fact that the conclusions of
economic analysis are often rejected out of hand because of the ethics seen to
sustain it. The political economy of the market, whether right or wrong in its
factual conclusions and predictions, is felt to be downright immoral by many.
It is said to be based on greed, to be devoid of human feelings, even to
undermine the very morality of hard work and self-disciplined calculation that
made its success. These misguided beliefs are nourished by the clash between ordinary
morality and the impersonal ethics of the market, or what Clark and Lee call
'mundane morality', as distinguished from 'magnanimous morality'. The latter
... can best be defined in terms of helping others in ways that satisfy three characteristics—helping intentionally, doing so at a personal sacrifice, and providing the help to identifiable beneficiaries. (Clark and Lee, page 3)
Mundane morality, on the other
hand, while being essential for the existence of society, is much less
attractive to ordinary people and in fact often not recognised as morality at
all. This is because, contrary to magnanimous morality, it has three
characteristics that contrast with the three set out above: it is
self-interested, profitable for both sides, and dispersed anonymously.
Now we can see why mundane
morality is seen under such an unfavourable light by people who do not
recognise that it has much more general and beneficent effects in society than
personal magnanimity. In sum,
[i]t is much easier to understand the persistent criticism of markets, and of the invisible hand justification for them, once the strong emotional attachment to magnanimous morality is considered. (pages 7-8)
Moving to a meta-plane
As I said when setting out the
first paradox to be considered in liberal democracy, it is a dangerous mistake
to limit oneself to holding that the rules of social life must be either
natural or rational. This will make the habits and institutions of the modern
economy look artificial because designed by nobody and that situations
resulting from the free decisions of individuals will be rejected as
undemocratic.
The best way to free society
from this vicious circle is to place the basic tools of civilization—language,
morals, law, and money—on a higher plane, as we did with the propositions of
the meta-language in the Liar's paradox. They must not be seen as part of the
object language and therefore to be judged according to the rules of our
biological makeup. They may be corrected and reformed by reason but very
carefully since our reason is itself the result of culture and can with
difficulty understand the byways of spontaneous evolution.
In sum, our personal instincts
as to what is natural should not lead us to disallow unpredictable social
evolution on a higher plane because its results feel artificial, and we should
wield the instrument of our reason with some care and diffidence.
Footnotes
1. Maxim Pinkovskiy and Xavier
Sala-i-Martin: "Parametric
Estimations of the World Distribution of Income". Working Paper 15433, October
2009, National Bureau of Economic Research. Other measures of poverty show a
similar degree of reduction. They also find that various measures of global
inequality have declined substantially and measures of global welfare
increased.
2. Of course, there is more than
a single cause to such progress, the main additional one being medical
advances, but there is no need here to underline the reciprocal relation
between freedom and scientific progress.
3. These reflections have been
inspired by the articles on "Paradoxes", the "Liar paradox"
and "Meta-languages" in J. Ferrater Mora (1982): Diccionario
de filosof¡a, vol.3. Alianza Editorial, Madrid.
4. I am using the 1979 Spanish
translation in vol. XXI of Freud's Collected Works, published by Amorrortu
Ediciones, Buenos Aires, pages 89-104.
5. The source given in the
Wikipedia article on Sigmund Freud is Jacoby, Russell (2009-09-21). "Freud's Visit to Clark
University". The Chronicle Review. (Retrieved 25 October 2013).
6. Friedrich A. Hayek, Law,
Legislation, and Liberty Volume 3: The Political Order of a Free People.
The University of Chicago Press, 1982.
7. Adam Ferguson: An Essay on the History of Civil
Society(1767). Available online at the Online Library of Liberty.
8. The matter of this and the
next paragraph I have expounded in more detail in my chapter titled
"Happiness is not within the Government's remit: The philosophical flaw in
happiness economics" of the book edited by Philip Booth: ... and
the Pursuit of Happiness. Institute of Economic Affairs (London): 2012.
9. Clark, J.R. and Lee, Dwight R.
(2011): "Markets and Morality".The Cato Journal, vol. 31, no.
1 (Winter), pages 1-25.
No comments:
Post a Comment