Stasis is not an option
by david friedman
Critics of free immigration worry that immigrants might change the country, make it more socialist, more crime ridden, more like the places they are coming from, but offer no strong reason to expect those particular effects. Leaving the place where you grew up to move somewhere very different is, after all, evidence that you prefer the latter. As I pointed out in one exchange, the Volokh brothers, associated with the popular libertarian/conservative legal blog the Volokh Conspiracy, are immigrants from the ex-Soviet Union. While Eugene and Sasha Volokh may be slightly more socialist than I am, they are much less socialist than most of their fellow academics, not entirely surprising given that they have experienced socialism at first hand.
Critics of free immigration worry that immigrants might change the country, make it more socialist, more crime ridden, more like the places they are coming from, but offer no strong reason to expect those particular effects. Leaving the place where you grew up to move somewhere very different is, after all, evidence that you prefer the latter. As I pointed out in one exchange, the Volokh brothers, associated with the popular libertarian/conservative legal blog the Volokh Conspiracy, are immigrants from the ex-Soviet Union. While Eugene and Sasha Volokh may be slightly more socialist than I am, they are much less socialist than most of their fellow academics, not entirely surprising given that they have experienced socialism at first hand.
The critics’ argument takes it for granted that change is presumptively
bad.
The same assumption appears implicitly in arguments over global warming. It
seems likely that the average temperature of the globe will go up by several
degrees C over the next hundred years due to increased Carbon dioxide in the
atmosphere, a change that will have both good and bad effects. If I had to
guess, my guess would be that the net effect will be positive, for at least two
reasons. The first is that human habitability is limited mostly by cold not
heat—the equator is populated, the poles are not. The second is that, for well
understood reasons, global warming can be expected to increase temperatures
more in cold places and at cold times than in warm. Combine those two and one
might guess that a somewhat warmer world would be, on the whole, more suited to
humans, not less. Here again, the explanation of the opposite view seems to me
to be the conservative mistake, the assumption that change is presumptively
bad. The same is true, I think, of concerns about a variety of other issues,
from fracking to cloning to GMO foods.
I call it a mistake, but perhaps that is unfair. We know that the present
is at least tolerable, since we are at present tolerating it. A change might
make things better, might make them worse, so why chance it? That sounds
like a plausible argument, but it contains a hidden assumption—that stasis is
an option, that if we do not have more immigration our cultural and political
circumstances will remain the same, that without anthropogenic CO2, climate
will stay what it currently is.
Both are demonstrably false. Over my lifetime the cultural and political
institutions of the U.S. have changed substantially for reasons that had little
to do with immigration. Over the past million years, the climate of the earth
has changed radically, time after time, for reasons that had nothing to do with
anthropogenic CO2. A rise in sea level of a foot or two would create problems
in some parts of the world, but not problems comparable to the effect of half a
mile of ice over the present locations of Chicago and London.
The left wing version of the conservative mistake comes with its own
pseudoscientific slogan, "the precautionary principle." It is the
rule that no decision should be made unless one can be confident that it will
not have substantial bad effects, that the lack of any good reason to believe
it will have such effects is not enough. At first glance it sounds plausible,
but a moment’s thought should convince you that it is internally incoherent.
The decision to permit nuclear power could have substantial bad effects. The
decision not to permit nuclear power could also have substantial bad effects.
If one takes the precautionary principle seriously, one is obligated to neither
permit nor forbid nuclear power and similarly with many other choices,
including acting or not acting to prevent global warming.
Continuing with that example, I have long argued, only partly in jest, that
the precautionary principle is itself a major source of global warming. Nuclear
power is the one source of power that does not produce CO2 and can be expanded
more or less without limit. A major factor restricting the growth of nuclear
power has been the precautionary principle, even if not always under that
name—hostility to permitting reactors to be built as long as there is any
chance that anything could go wrong. That example demonstrates my more general
point—that stasis is not an option. The world is going to change whether or not
we permit nuclear power and there is no a priori reason to
expect the changes if we do not permit it to be worse than those if we do.
I am not arguing that there is never a good reason to fear change—sometimes
a change can be reasonably predicted to have bad consequences. I am arguing that
much opposition to change, across a wide range of different topics and
disputes, is based on the mistaken assumption that if only that particular
change is prevented, the next year, the next decade, the next century, will be
more or less the same as the present.
That is very
unlikely.
No comments:
Post a Comment