by Garrett Hardin
In 1974 the general public got a
graphic illustration of the “tragedy of the commons” in satellite photos of the
earth. Pictures of northern Africa showed an irregular dark patch 390 square
miles in area. Ground-level investigation revealed a fenced area inside of
which there was plenty of grass. Outside, the ground cover had been devastated.
The explanation was simple. The
fenced area was private property, subdivided into five portions. Each year the
owners moved their animals to a new section. Fallow periods of four years gave
the pastures time to recover from the grazing. The owners did this because they
had an incentive to take care of their land. But no one owned the land outside
the ranch. It was open to nomads and their herds. Though knowing nothing of Karl
Marx, the herdsmen followed his famous advice of 1875: “To each according to
his needs.” Their needs were uncontrolled and grew with the increase in the
number of animals. But supply was governed by nature and decreased
drastically during the drought of the early 1970s. The herds exceeded the natural “carrying capacity” of their environment, soil was compacted and eroded, and “weedy” plants, unfit for cattle consumption, replaced good plants. Many cattle died, and so did humans.
drastically during the drought of the early 1970s. The herds exceeded the natural “carrying capacity” of their environment, soil was compacted and eroded, and “weedy” plants, unfit for cattle consumption, replaced good plants. Many cattle died, and so did humans.
The rational explanation for such
ruin was given more than 170 years ago. In 1832 William Forster Lloyd, a
political economist at Oxford University, looking at the recurring devastation
of common (i.e., not privately owned) pastures in England, asked: “Why are the
cattle on a common so puny and stunted? Why is the common itself so bare-worn,
and cropped so differently from the adjoining inclosures?”
Lloyd’s answer assumed that each
human exploiter of the common was guided by self-interest. At the point when
the carrying capacity of the commons was fully reached, a herdsman might ask
himself, “Should I add another animal to my herd?” Because the herdsman owned
his animals, the gain of so doing would come solely to him. But the loss
incurred by overloading the pasture would be “commonized” among all the
herdsmen. Because the privatized gain would exceed his share of the commonized
loss, a self-seeking herdsman would add another animal to his herd. And
another. And reasoning in the same way, so would all the other herdsmen.
Ultimately, the common property would be ruined.
Even when herdsmen understand the
long-run consequences of their actions, they generally are powerless to prevent
such damage without some coercive means of controlling the actions of each
individual. Idealists may appeal to individuals caught in such a system, asking
them to let the long-term effects govern their actions. But each individual
must first survive in the short run. If all decision makers were unselfish and
idealistic calculators, a distribution governed by the rule “to each according
to his needs” might work. But such is not our world. As James Madison said in
1788, “If men were angels, no Government would be necessary” (Federalist, no.
51). That is, if all men were angels. But in a world in which all resources are
limited, a single nonangel in the commons spoils the environment for all.
The spoilage process comes in two
stages. First, the non-angel gains from his “competitive advantage” (pursuing
his own interest at the expense of others) over the angels. Then, as the once
noble angels realize that they are losing out, some of them renounce their
angelic behavior. They try to get their share out of the commons before
competitors do. In other words, every workable distribution system must meet
the challenge of human self-interest. An unmanaged commons in a world of
limited material wealth and unlimited desires inevitably ends in ruin.
Inevitability justifies the epithet “tragedy,” which I introduced in 1968.
Whenever a distribution system
malfunctions, we should be on the lookout for some sort of commons. Fish
populations in the oceans have been decimated because people have interpreted
the “freedom of the seas” to include an unlimited right to fish them. The fish
were, in effect, a commons. In the 1970s, nations began to assert their sole
right to fish out to two hundred miles from shore (instead of the traditional
three miles). But these exclusive rights did not eliminate the problem of the
commons. They merely restricted the commons to individual nations. Each nation
still has the problem of allocating fishing rights among its own people on a
noncommonized basis. If each government allowed ownership of fish within a
given area, so that an owner could sue those who encroach on his fish, owners
would have an incentive to refrain from overfishing. But governments do not do
that. Instead, they often estimate the maximum sustainable yield and then
restrict fishing either to a fixed number of days or to a fixed aggregate
catch. Both systems result in a vast overinvestment in fishing boats and
equipment as individual fishermen compete to catch fish quickly.
Some of the common pastures of old
England were protected from ruin by the tradition of stinting—limiting each
herdsman to a fixed number of animals (not necessarily the same for all). Such
cases are spoken of as “managed commons,” which is the logical equivalent of
socialism. Viewed this way, socialism may be good or bad, depending on the
quality of the management. As with all things human, there is no guarantee of
permanent excellence. The old Roman warning must be kept constantly in mind:
Quis custodiet ipsos custodes? (Who shall watch the watchers themselves?)
Under special circumstances even an
unmanaged commons may work well. The principal requirement is that there be no
scarcity of goods. Early frontiersmen in the American colonies killed as much
game as they wanted without endangering the supply, the multiplication of which
kept pace with their needs. But as the human population grew larger, hunting
and trapping had to be managed. Thus, the ratio of supply to demand is
critical.
The scale of the commons (the number
of people using it) also is important, as an examination of Hutterite
communities reveals. These devoutly religious people in the northwestern United
States live by Marx’s formula: “From each according to his ability, to each
according to his needs.” (They give no credit to Marx, however; similar
language can be found several places in the Bible.) At first glance Hutterite
colonies appear to be truly unmanaged commons.
But appearances are deceiving. The number of people included in the decision unit is crucial. As the size of a colony approaches 150, individual Hutterites begin to undercontribute from their abilities and overdemand for their needs. The experience of Hutterite communities indicates that below 150 people, the distribution system can be managed by shame; above that approximate number, shame loses its effectiveness.
But appearances are deceiving. The number of people included in the decision unit is crucial. As the size of a colony approaches 150, individual Hutterites begin to undercontribute from their abilities and overdemand for their needs. The experience of Hutterite communities indicates that below 150 people, the distribution system can be managed by shame; above that approximate number, shame loses its effectiveness.
If any group could make a
commonistic system work, an earnest religious community like the Hutterites
should be able to. But numbers are the nemesis. In Madison’s terms, nonangelic
members then corrupt the angelic. Whenever size alters the properties of a
system, engineers speak of a “scale effect.” A scale effect, based on human
psychology, limits the workability of commonistic systems.
Even when the shortcomings of the
commons are understood, areas remain in which reform is difficult. No one owns
the Earth’s atmosphere. Therefore, it is treated as a common dump into which everyone
may discharge wastes. Among the unwanted consequences of this behavior are acid
rain, the greenhouse effect, and the erosion of the Earth’s protective ozone
layer. Industries and even nations are apt to regard the cleansing of
industrial discharges as prohibitively expensive. The oceans are also treated
as a common dump. Yet continuing to defend the freedom to pollute will
ultimately lead to ruin for all. Nations are just beginning to evolve controls
to limit this damage.
The tragedy of the commons also
arose in the savings and loan (S&L) crisis. The federal government created
this tragedy by forming the Federal Savings and Loan Insurance Corporation
(FSLIC). The FSLIC relieved S&L depositors of worry about their money by
guaranteeing that it would use taxpayers’ money to repay them if an S&L
went broke. In effect, the government made the taxpayers’ money into a commons
that S&Ls and their depositors could exploit. S&Ls had the incentive to
make overly risky investments, and depositors did not have to care because they
did not bear the cost. This, combined with faltering federal surveillance of
the S&Ls, led to widespread failures. The losses were “commonized” among
the nation’s taxpayers, with serious consequences to the federal budget (see savings
and loan crisis).
Congestion on public roads that do
not charge tolls is another example of a government-created tragedy of the
commons. If roads were privately owned, owners would charge tolls and people
would take the toll into account in deciding whether to use them. Owners of
private roads would probably also engage in what is called peak-load pricing,
charging higher prices during times of peak demand and lower prices at other
times. But because governments own roads that they finance with tax dollars,
they normally do not charge tolls. The government makes roads into a commons.
The result is congestion.
About the Author
The late Garrett Hardin was
professor emeritus of human ecology at the University of California at Santa
Barbara. He died in 2003.
Further Reading
Berkes, Fikret. Common Property
Resources. London: Belhaven Press, 1989.
Hardin, Garrett. Filters Against
Folly. New York: Viking-Penguin, 1985.
Hardin, Garrett. “Living on a
Lifeboat.” BioScience 24 (1974): 561–568.
Hardin, Garrett. “The Tragedy of the
Commons.” Science 162 (1968): 1243–1248.
Hardin, Garrett, and John Baden,
eds. Managing the Commons. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1977.
Hiatt, Howard H. America’s Health in
the Balance. New York: Harper and Row, 1987.
McCay, Bonnie J., and James M.
Acheson, eds. The Question of the Commons. Tucson: University of Arizona Press,
1987.
McGoodwin, James R. Crisis in the
World’s Fisheries. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1990.
Ostrom, Elinor. Governing the
Commons. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
No comments:
Post a Comment