by David Greenwald
As a teacher in a public high school, I am daily
confronted with the lamentable realities of state-monopoly education. Student
apathy, methodological stagnation, bureaucratic inefficiency,
textbook-publishing cartels, obsessive preoccupation with grades, coercive
relationships, and rigid, sanitized curricula are just a few of the more
obvious problems, attended by the cold-shower disillusionment and gradual
burnout among teachers to which they almost invariably lead.
While outcomes such as these are certainly tragic, the
process that produces them is not exactly the stuff of Greek theater. There is
no climactic battle, no cathartic denouement, no salvific moral lesson to be
taken home when the curtain falls, and seldom are there any readily
identifiable heroes or villains. It is not a single, epic calamity but a
thousand trivial defeats a day, each too mundane and too quickly obscured by
its successor to be considered noteworthy. Like a bad movie, public education
somehow manages to be both tragic and boring. It is only its cumulative result
that would have impressed Sophocles.
Oddly enough, although there is overwhelming public support for compulsory, tax-funded schooling, enthusiasm for what actually goes on in public schools is noticeably lacking. Not only are they generally acknowledged to be falling short in their efforts to produce an enlightened citizenry, but it is even conceded that they have failed in what is ostensibly their most exalted mission: the provision of equal opportunity for all via a standardized system of mass instruction in which all students receive the same basic set of knowledge and skills. Nor has this indictment originated solely from among the ranks of those opposed to egalitarianism on principle. To the contrary, it is largely the refrain of embittered progressives for whom "free" universal education has long been the desideratum of social justice, and who cannot understand how the behemoth they so vigorously midwifed into existence and then wet-nursed for a century could have so thoroughly betrayed their loftiest and most cherished ideal.
Yet ironically, it is the unassailable faith in the
achievability of precisely this ideal of universal equality that immunizes
public education against every reasonable argument advanced in opposition to
it. Notwithstanding its manifest shortcomings, none of which has found a remedy
despite decades of legislative reform, hardly anyone is prepared to see this
system replaced by anything resembling a real market in education due to the
deeply held conviction that that those of lesser material means either would
not be able to afford market-based schooling or, in the very best case, would
receive only substandard services inadequate to the task of ensuring equality
of economic opportunity later in life. It is a further irony, though hardly
surprising, that neither the economic knowledge nor the analytic discernment
necessary for an examination of these claims has ever been or will ever be
taught in a public school. No emperor willingly trains his own subjects to
recognize nakedness when they see it.
Given this state of affairs, it devolves on individuals, both within and outside of the school system, to educate others about education. In what follows I will attempt to address what I see as the three primary objections raised against the idea of market-based education:
1. that educational services on the market would be at a premium, with prices high enough to exclude at least the lowest-income strata of society;
2. that even if the less affluent could afford some market-based education, it would be of a substantially inferior quality to that received by wealthier consumers of educational services; and
3. that the lack of a universal curriculum and standardized criteria of achievement would render the market incapable of providing the equality of opportunity that public education, however unsatisfactorily, at least aims in principle to ensure.
We will examine each of these arguments in turn. As
will be shown, the first two rest on a misunderstanding of markets, while the
third stems from a grossly distorted concept of education from which, if they
took the time to examine it closely, probably even most progressives would
recoil in horror.
Argument 1: Affordability
In order to understand why educational services on a
free market would as a rule be priced well within the reach of the vast
majority of income earners, we must first ask why the market produces anything
at all for such persons. Since it is obvious that the wealthiest few have far
more purchasing power per capita than those in the middle- and lower-income
strata, why does the market not produce only for the former group and leave the
latter two homeless and starving? Why is sugar, once a luxury of the rich,
today a household item so widely and cheaply available that the US government
feels called on to impose tariffs on imports and buy up domestic surpluses to
keep the price artificially high? Why is the same kilobyte of computer memory
that cost around $45 twenty years ago today priced at a fraction of a cent?
The simple answer is this: competition. When a good first appears on the market,
the supply of it is strictly limited. To the extent that consumers value it
highly, they will bid against each other for the minimal stock available,
causing the price to rise until all but the wealthiest consumers drop out of
the market. As long as there is no expansion of supply, and assuming the
consumers do not change their valuations, the good will remain a luxury of the
rich.
However, it is precisely this condition that provides
producers with the incentive to increase production of the product. The high
price yields supernormal profits that draw venture capitalists and
entrepreneurs into that line of production, thereby increasing the supply,
lowering the price, and most importantly, bringing exponentially greater
numbers of consumers into the market. This process continues until
that portion of profits that exceeds the general rate prevailing in other
industries disappears, bringing the expansion to a halt. But by that time, the
good has long since ceased to be a toy for the rich. To paraphrase
Mises, yesterday's
luxury has become today's necessity.
Of course, while this process works in essentially the
same way for all goods, some goods — diamonds, for example — tend to remain
luxury items indefinitely due to the high cost of producing them. It is, after
all, the consumers who, in the aggregate, must ultimately pay for any lasting
expansion of industry. If the capital expenditures necessary for the production
of a good exceed the willingness or ability of the consumers to offset them, no
sustained increase in the supply of that good will be possible.
So how would this dynamic work on a market for
education? Assuming that educational services as such would be given high
priority on the value scales of most consumers, would the cost of producing
them keep them priced beyond the means of the typical wage-earner? Here we must
be particularly careful not to engage in what psychologists call static
thinking. We must ask ourselves, not how much it would cost for private
entrepreneurs to produce curricula and instruction as these are presently constituted, but rather to what
extent and in what ways schooling in its current form squanders resources, and
how it might be streamlined and otherwise improved in the crucible of free
competition.
One point is clear: the greater and more numerous the
inefficiencies of the current system, the more radical its transformation by
the market would be. And just how inefficient is the present
system? Well, who runs it? On what principles does it operate? Does it allow
students the freedom, for example, to take courses in what they are most
interested in and eschew subjects they do not wish to study? Or does it rather
saddle them with a bloated, one-size-fits-all curriculum prodigiously crammed
full of skills and information they neither need nor want, thereby creating artificial
demand for teachers and administrative staff, stimulating construction of
needlessly large (or simply needless) facilities, boosting energy consumption
and capital maintenance costs, and so forth? To get an idea of the sorts of
"practical competencies" students in today's public and
state-regulated high schools are expected to (pretend to) master and retain for
use in later life,[1] here is a randomly-selected excerpt from
the scintillating epistle "Texas Essential Knowledge and Skills for
Mathematics," issued by the Texas Education Agency:
§111.35. Precalculus (One-Half to One Credit).
c. Knowledge and skills.
a. The student defines functions, describes characteristics of functions, and translates among verbal, numerical, graphical, and symbolic representations of functions, including polynomial, rational, power (including radical), exponential, logarithmic, trigonometric, and piecewise-defined functions. The student is expected to:
A. describe parent functions symbolically and graphically, including f(x) = xn, f(x) = 1n x, f(x) = loga x, f(x) = 1/x, f(x) = ex, f(x) = |x|, f(x) = ax, f(x) = sin x, f(x) = arcsin x, etc.;
B. determine the domain and range of functions using graphs, tables, and symbols;
C. describe symmetry of graphs of even and odd functions;
D. recognize and use connections among significant values of a function (zeros, maximum values, minimum values, etc.), points on the graph of a function, and the symbolic representation of a function; and
E. investigate the concepts of continuity, end behavior, asymptotes, and limits and connect these characteristics to functions represented graphically and numerically.
Got all that?
Of course, administrative costs and restrictions on
entry and labor-market flexibility also impact cost-efficiency. How do public
schools hold up in these areas? Are their operational rules and procedures
clear, concise, and easy to follow? Or does it take, say, 670 pages
and whole
cadres of lawyers, consultants, and administrative support staff just to
implement a single program? Regarding entry, how easy is it to qualify as a
member of the academy? Is anyone who demonstrates a potential aptitude for
meeting the educational demands of students given the opportunity to try to do
so? Or is club membership restricted by legal quotas and licensure requirements
necessitating lengthy and expensive formal training?

And how flexible is the labor market? Can an
underperforming or incompetent employee be readily replaced? Or does even a
mere suspension require a hearing before a three-member commission?[2]
We do not have space here to speculate on all the
optimizing innovations creative entrepreneurs might come up with, and to do so
would be presumptuous in any case. As John Hasnas has pointed out, if we could
forecast the future market accurately, our very ability to do this would be the
greatest possible justification for central planning.[3] Suffice it to say that today's public and
government-regulated private schools dissipate resources with a profligacy that
would have made Ludwig
II blush. We can
hardly claim, then, that these institutions — whose costs are externalized onto
the whole society — are paragons of affordability. Yet education is not a
capital-intensive industry, and market competition would surely eliminate most
of this waste in short order, allowing educational entrepreneurs to reduce
their costs, lower their prices, and take advantage of economies of scale. As
for those few who might still be unable to pay, lower prices would mean that
private scholarships, grants, and student loans would be available in greater abundance than they are today, and the
latter would no longer require ten years of indentured servitude to pay off.
Just as with sugar, automobiles, civil aviation, and
cell phones,[4] so too in education high initial profits
would draw competition, increase supply, reduce cost, and multiply innovation.
There is no reason for market-driven educational services tailored specifically
to the desires of those who consume them to be prohibitively expensive.[5]
Argument 2: Quality
A second argument against leaving education to the
market is that to do so would result in grave disparities in quality of
service. The rich, it is said, would get steak, while the poor got rump roast.
Of course, there is a kernel of truth in this. The more you are prepared to
offer for something, the more quality you are in a position to demand. The
market is indeed a place where the principle embodied in the cliché "You
get what you pay for" prevails.
But what exactly do you pay for?
The answer to this question is not necessarily obvious. To illustrate, I offer
a personal example.
Many years ago, I worked at a tavern-style restaurant
that was part of a nationwide chain. With its eclectic menu, modest prices, and
dollar-a-mug draft beers, it was a place where families could go on a budget,
and weekend drinkers could go on a binge. Not exactly Alain
Ducasse, but we did
offer a steak (T-bone, as I recall) for around $10. What is interesting about
this is that right next door was a more upscale steakhouse that also served
T-bone; only this one went for something like $22. Nothing unusual about that,
but here's the catch: both restaurants were owned by the same company and both served exactly the same T-bone steak.
At first blush, this seems absurd. Why would any
company compete with itself? And why, for that matter, would anyone in his
right mind pay $22 for a steak he could get for less than half that just by
walking across the parking lot? Situations like this have led to calls for
governments to step in and "protect" consumers from their own
"irrationality." But there is nothing irrational going on here. The
two restaurants were not in competition, because they served different
clientele, and patrons had definite reasons for the choices they made about
which restaurant to patronize. Ours wanted to cut the frills, sit at the bar,
and save money; theirs were willing to pay more than double the price for the
plush seats, subdued ambience, and tuxedoed waiters. The essential thing,
however, is that both were eating the same steak.
The relationship between price and quality is
therefore not as straightforward as we might imagine. It is certainly true that
you get what you pay for, but it is equally true that you pay for what you get.
To be sure, on the education market, those with the wherewithal could attend
schools equipped with indoor swimming pools, tennis courts, amphitheaters, and
state-of-the-art IT. But this does not mean that everyone else could not make
do with less extravagance and still get the same basic service.
Of course, all this in no way suggests that quality of
educational services would be identical. Such
a conclusion would be absurd. What we have demonstrated is simply the
fallacious reasoning behind the common assumption that where price is low,
product must be unsatisfactory. What does not satisfy is not profitable.
Products and services that do not meet the needs of consumers — rich and poor —
will soon have, not a low price, but no price.
Argument 3: Opportunity
We now turn to a final argument for public education
that goes beyond economics, though even here there is a parallel. Deeply rooted
in the belief that justice means equality and equality means identical
circumstances, this view holds that educational standards and curricula must be
essentially uniform for everyone if all students are to be given the same
opportunity to succeed in life. Here, the anticipated failure of the market
lies, not in its high prices or disparate quality, but in its presumably
excessive flexibility and diversity. In essence, this argument is really
nothing more than a special case of the more general socialist contempt for the
division of labor. But what is the "division of labor" in education?
What is its meaning, and why should we fear its emergence?
We are accustomed to conceiving of education, not as
an abstraction, but as a "real thing" existing in the world outside;
a commodity possessed by some people whom we call "teachers" and
transferred, more or less mechanically, to other people called "students."
This habit of thought is reflected in our language: it is far more common to
talk about getting an education than
about becoming educated. Yet the greatest thinkers in
this area have repeatedly emphasized that education is, in fact, a process of
becoming. This is what Maria Montessori meant when she said that if our
definition of education proceeds along the same antiquated lines of a mere transmission
of knowledge, there is little to be hoped from it in the bettering of man's
future. For what is the use of transmitting knowledge if the individual's total
development lags behind?
Montessori urged an approach to pedagogy that would
"help toward the complete unfolding of life," and "rigorously …
avoid the arrest of spontaneous movements and the imposition of arbitrary
tasks."
John Dewey expressed similar views. In his seminal
work Democracy and Education, Dewey
places the onus of responsibility for education squarely on the shoulders of
the individual student:
One is mentally an individual only as he has his own
purpose and problem, and does his own thinking. The phrase "think for
oneself" is a pleonasm. Unless one does it for oneself, it isn't thinking.
Only by a pupil's own observations, reflections, framing and testing of
suggestions can what he already knows be amplified and rectified. Thinking is
as much an individual matter as is the digestion of food. [Moreover], there are
variations of point of view, of appeal of objects, and of mode of attack, from
person to person. When these variations are suppressed in the alleged interests
of uniformity, and an attempt is made to have a single mold of method of study
and recitation, mental confusion and artificiality inevitably result.
Originality is gradually destroyed, confidence in one's own quality of mental
operation is undermined, and a docile subjection to the opinion of others is
inculcated, or else ideas run wild. (p. 311–12)
For both Dewey and Montessori, education starts from
the inside and moves outward.[6] Its purpose is to stimulate discovery and development of the personal resources
latent within the self by allowing the student to experience the myriad
possibilities for bringing them to bear creatively on the external world.
This means that becoming educated is not a matter of
passively acquiring what is given, but of actively discovering what one has to
give. It means that education does not create opportunity; opportunity creates education.
Regimentation and uniformity must therefore be
jettisoned entirely; the individual must reign supreme within the sphere of his
own development. The function of the school is to provide a stable environment
rich in stimuli across a broad spectrum of disciplines, while the role of the
teacher becomes primarily that of the observer who watches as closely — and
intervenes as sparingly — as possible.
From this it follows that no two individuals would or
could possibly educate themselves in exactly the same way. The self-directed
intellectual, aesthetic, and spiritual explorations of millions of people
simultaneously thus result in an unfathomable diversification of interests and
activities that amounts to an educational "division of labor" — one
that supports and enhances the division of labor of the market economy, and is
in fact its logical precursor.
It must surely be obvious that such a philosophy is in
every way wholly incompatible with systems of compulsory or universalized
schooling aimed at "equalizing opportunity," and moreover, that even
to use the word opportunity in connection with compulsion or regimentation is
to abuse language, otherwise we might just as well reinstate slavery in the
name of providing equal "employment opportunity."
Education, if it is to be worthy of the name, demands
a method opposite to that of bureaucratic management and entirely
irreconcilable with it. It requires flexibility, parsimony, innovation, and
above all, a means of daily subjecting the producers of educational services to
the competition of their peers and the approval or disapproval of their
clients.
It requires, in other words, the free market.
Conclusion
In Slovenia where I teach, the verb "to
learn" literally translates "to teach oneself."
If the truth behind this linguistic convention were widely recognized, it would
discredit the very premise on which all systems of public education are
founded. But, as the great economist Frédéric Bastiat warned more than a
century and a half ago, there is a pronounced tendency when confronted with
important questions to consider only what is seen and ignore that which is not
seen. And this just as true in education as it is in economics. We see students
go to school day after day for 12 years, do as they're told, get their
diplomas, and finally go on to do something with their lives. Perhaps from our
vantage point it does not look so bad. But what we do not see is what they
might have become had they been allowed to be the architects of their own fate
from the beginning.
Notes
[1] Note that
on the market, service providers do not "expect" anything from their
customers except payment. It is rather the consumer who expects satisfactory
performance from the provider.
[2] Block,
Walter and Young, A. 1999. "Enterprising education: Doing away with the public
school system."International
Journal of Value-Based Management, vol. 12, pp. 195–207.
[3] Hasnas, J.
1995. "The Myth of the Rule of Law." In Stringham, E.P. (Ed.), Anarchy and the Law: The Political Economy of Choice,
pp. 163–192. Oakland, CA: The Independent Institute.
[5] Those
still in doubt should visit the Mises Academy, which has put all of its summer
courses on sale for tuition fees ranging from $59 to $79
per class. Ever heard of an accredited — that is, state-cartelized — university
having a sale? Neither have I.
[6] One of the
most salient insights of both Montessori and Dewey is the theory of
concentrated attention, according to which the one indispensable prerequisite
of education is that children be allowed to focus on an activity for as long as
they are absorbed in it. Both philosophers agree that what we call education
can only occur as a result of this absorption, and so, just as it is the first
duty of the physician to do no harm, so it is the first task of the
teacher not to interrupt. Of course, the modern school is
set up to be nothing but an endless series of interruptions. Like the
thought-disruption device planted in the ear of the protagonist in Kurt
Vonnegut's story "Harrison Bergeron," the
school day is broken up into a hodgepodge of unrelated subjects and types of
activity, disrupted every 45 minutes by the Pavlovian ringing of a bell. Under
these conditions, nothing resembling what Montessori and Dewey would call
education can take place. For more on this, see Kirkpatrick, J. 2008. Montessori, Dewey, and Capitalism: Educational Theory for
a Free Market in Education. Claremont, CA: TLJ Books.
No comments:
Post a Comment