Introduction
In recent years, economists have invaded other
intellectual disciplines and, in the dubious name of "science," have
employed staggeringly oversimplified assumptions in order to make sweeping and
provocative conclusions about fields they know very little about. This is a
modern form of "economic imperialism" in the realm of the intellect.
Almost always, the bias of this economic imperialism has been quantitative and
implicitly Benthamite, in which poetry and pushpin are reduced to a single
level, and which amply justifies the gibe of Oscar Wilde about cynics, that
they (economists) know the price of everything and the value of nothing. The
results of this economic imperialism have been particularly ludicrous in the
fields of sex, the family, and education.
So why then does the present author, not a Benthamite,
now have the temerity to tackle a field as arcane, abstruse, metaphysical, and
seemingly unrelated to economics as hermeneutics? Here my plea is the always
legitimate one of self-defense. Discipline after discipline, from literature to
political theory to philosophy to history, have been invaded by an arrogant
band of hermeneuticians, and now even economics is under assault. Hence, this
article is in the nature of a counterattack.
To begin, the dictionary definition of hermeneutics is
the age-old discipline of interpreting the Bible. Until the 1920s or 1930s,
indeed, hermeneutics was confined to theologians and departments of religion.
But things changed with the advent of the murky German doctrines of Martin
Heidegger, the founder of modern hermeneutics. With the death of Heidegger, the
apostolic succession of head of the hermeneutical movement fell upon his
student, Hans-Georg Gadamer, who still wears this mantle.
The greatest success of the hermeneutical movement has
been achieved in recent decades, beginning in the closely related movement of
"deconstructionism" in literary criticism. Headed by the French
theorists Michel Foucault, Paul Ricoeur, and Jacques Derrida, deconstructionism
in the Western Hemisphere is led by the formidable Department at Yale
University, from which it has spread to conquer most of the English-literature
departments in the United States and Canada. The essential message of
deconstructionism and hermeneutics can be variously summed up as nihilism,
relativism, and solipsism. That is, either there is no objective truth or, if
there is, we can never discover it. With each person being bound to his own
subjective views, feelings, history, and so on, there is no method of
discovering objective truth. In literature, the most elemental procedure of
literary criticism (that is, trying to figure out what a given author meant to
say) becomes impossible. Communication between writer and reader similarly
becomes hopeless; furthermore, not only can no reader ever figure out what an
author meant to say, but even the author does not know or understand what he
himself meant to say, so fragmented, confused, and driven is each particular
individual. So, since it is impossible to figure out what Shakespeare, Conrad,
Plato, Aristotle, or Machiavelli meant, what becomes the point of either
reading or writing literary or philosophical criticism?
It is an interesting question, one that the
deconstructionists and other hermeneuticians have of course not been able to
answer. By their own avowed declaration, it is impossible for
deconstructionists to understand literary texts or, for example, for Gadamer to
understand Aristotle, upon whom he has nevertheless written on at enormous
length. As the English philosopher Jonathan Barnes has pointed out in his
brilliant and witty critique of hermeneutics, Gadamer, not having anything to
say about Aristotle or his works, is reduced to reporting his own subjective
musings — a sort of lengthy account of "what Aristotle means to me."
Setting aside the hermeneutical problem of whether or not Gadamer can know even what Aristotle means to him, we push
back the problem another notch. Namely, why in the world should anyone but
Gadamer, except possibly his mother or wife, be in the least interested in the
question of what Aristotle means to him? And even in the improbable event that
we were interested in this earth-shattering question,
we would in any case be prevented on hermeneutical principles from
understanding Gadamer's answer.
Deconstruction and hermeneutics are clearly
self-refuting on many levels. If we cannot understand the meaning of any texts,
then why are we bothering with trying to understand or to take seriously the
works or doctrines of authors who aggressively proclaim their own
incomprehensibility?
Incomprehensibility
Indeed, a crucial point about the hermeneuticians is
that, for them, incomprehensibility is a self-fulfilling prophecy. As a
colleague of mine ruefully told me: "I have read everything on
hermeneutics I can lay my hands on, and I understand no more about it than I
did when I first started." Even in a profession — philosophy — not exactly
famous for its sparkle or lucidity, one of the most remarkable qualities of the
hermeneuticians is their horrendous and incomparably murky style. Stalactites
and stalagmites of jargon words are piled upon each other in a veritable
kitchen midden of stupefying and meaningless prose. Hermeneuticians seem to be
incapable of writing a clear English, or indeed a clear German sentence.
Critics of hermeneutics — such as Jonathan Barnes or David Gordon[1] —are understandably moved to satire, to stating
or quoting hermeneutical tracts and then "translating" them into
simple English, where invariably they are revealed as either banal or idiotic.
At first, I thought that these German hermeneuticians
were simply ill-served by their translators into English. But my German friends
assure me that Heidegger, Gadamer, et al. are equally unintelligible in the
original. Indeed, in a recently translated essay, Eric Voegelin, a philosopher
not normally given to scintillating wit, was moved to ridicule Heidegger's
language. Referring to Heidegger's master work, Sein und
Zeit (Being and Time), Voegelin refers to the meaningless but
insistent repetition of a veritable philosophical dictionary of phrases as the Anwesen des Answesenden ("the presence of
that which is present"), the Dingen des Dings ("the
thinging of the thing"), the Nichten des Nichts ("the
nothinging of the nothing"), and finally to the zeigenden Zeichen des Zeigzeugs ("the
Pointing sign of the pointing implement"), all of which is designed, says
Voegelin, to whip up the reader "into a reality-withdrawing state of
linguistic delirium."[2]
On Gadamer and the hermeneuticians, Jonathan Barnes
writes:
What, then, are the characteristic features of hermeneutical philosophy? Its enemies will wade in with adjectives like empty, vapid, dreamy, woolly, rhetorical. Gadamer himself tells an uncharacteristic story. At the end of a seminar on Cajetan, Heidegger once startled his devoted audience by posing the question: "What is being?" "We sat there staring and shaking our heads over the absurdity of the question." Quite right too, say the enemies of hermeneutics: the question is perfectly absurd. But Gadamer has only a frail sense of the absurd, and his own readers ought to react as he once — but alas, only once — reacted to Heidegger.
Barnes goes on to say that Gadamer admits "that
his thought has sometimes been less than pellucid." He further quotes
Gadamer as saying:
Certainly I sometimes spoke over my pupils' heads and put too many complications into my train of thought. Even earlier my friends had invented a new scientific measure, the "Gad," which designated a settled measure of unnecessary complications.
Barnes adds that:
Some may prefer to this self-congratulatory little story a remark which Gadarner makes of his younger self: "Despite my title of doctor, I was still a 22-year old boy who thought rather murky thinking, and who still did not really know what was going on."
At this point we may cite Sir Karl Popper on G.W.F.
Hegel, who counts along with Friedrich Schleiermacher as at least a
great-grandfather of hermeneutics. What Popper lacks in satiric gifts he makes
up in the vehemence of the scorn that he heaps upon the legion of his
philosophical enemies, real or imagined. After denouncing Hegel's
"high-flown gibberish" and "imbecile fancies," Popper
quotes with obvious relish the attack on Hegel by his contemporary Schopenhauer
as:
a flat-headed, insipid, nauseating, illiterate charlatan, who reached the pinnacle of audacity in scribbling together and dishing up the craziest mystifying nonsense. This nonsense has been noisily proclaimed as immortal wisdom by mercenary followers and readily accepted as such by all fools, who thus joined into as perfect a chorus of admiration as had ever been heard before.[4]
Why this enormous acclaim and influence exerted by
mystifying nonsense? In addition to noting its establishment in the interests
of the Prussian state, Popper offers the following explanation:
For some reason, philosophers have kept around themselves, even in our day, something of the atmosphere of the magician. Philosophy is considered a strange and abstruse kind of thing, dealing with those mysteries with which religion deals, but not in a way which can be "revealed unto babes" or to common people; it is considered to be too profound for that, and to be the religion and theology of the intellectuals, of the learned and wise.[5]
For a final citation on the incomprehensibility of
hermeneutics, let us turn to the witty and devastating demolition by H.L.
Mencken of Thorstein Veblen, another early protohermeneutician and an
institutionalist opponent of the idea of economic law. In the course of an
essay featuring the "translation" into English of Veblen's
indecipherable prose, Mencken wrote that what was truly remarkable about
Veblen's ideas:
was the astoundingly grandiose and rococo manner of their statement, the almost unbelievable tediousness and flatulence of the gifted headmaster's prose, his unprecedented talent for saying nothing in an august and heroic manner.…
Marx, I daresay, had said a good deal of it long
before him, and what Marx overlooked had been said over and over again by his
heirs and assigns. But Marx, at this business, labored under a technical
handicap; he wrote in German, a language he actually understood. Prof. Veblen
submitted himself to no such disadvantage. Though born, I believe, in these
States, and resident here all his life, he achieved the effect, perhaps without
employing the means, of thinking in some unearthly foreign language — say Swahili,
Sumerian or Old Bulgarian — and then painfully clawing his thoughts into a
copious and uncertain but book-learned English. The result was a style that
affected the higher cerebral centers like a constant roll of subway expresses.
The second result was a sort of bewildered numbness of the senses, as before
some fabulous and unearthly marvel. And the third result, if I make no mistake,
was the celebrity of the professor as a Great Thinker.[6]
Collectivism
Marx, in fact, has been hailed by the hermeneuticians
as one of the grandfathers of the movement. In 1985, for example, at the annual
meeting of the Western Political Science Association in Las Vegas, virtually
every paper offered in political theory was a hermeneutical one. A paradigmatic
title would be "Political Life as a Text: Hermeneutics and Interpretation
in Marx, Heidegger, Gadamer, and Foucault." (Substitute freely such names
as Ricoeur and Derrida, with an occasional bow to Habermas.)
I do not believe it an accident that Karl Marx is considered
one of the great hermeneuticians. This century has seen a series of devastating
setbacks to Marxism, to its pretensions to "scientific truth," and to
its theoretical propositions as well as to its empirical assertions and
predictions. If Marxism has been riddled both in theory and in practice, then
what can Marxian cultists fall back on? It seems to me that hermeneutics fits
very well into an era that we might, following a Marxian gambit about
capitalism, call "late Marxism" or Marxism-in-decline. Marxism is not
true and is not science, but so what? The hermeneuticians tell us that nothing
is objectively true, and therefore that all views and propositions are
subjective, relative to the whims and feelings of each individual.
So why should Marxian yearnings not be equally as
valid as anyone else's? By the way of hermeneutics, these yearnings cannot be
subject to refutation. And since there is no objective reality, and since
reality is created by every man's subjective interpretations, then all social problems
reduce to personal and nonrational tastes. If, then, hermeneutical Marxists
find capitalism ugly and unlovely, and they find socialism beautiful, why
should they not attempt to put their personal esthetic preferences into action?
If they feel that socialism is beautiful, what can stop them, especially since
there are no laws of economics or truths of political philosophy to place
obstacles in their path?
It is no accident that, with the exception of a
handful of contemporary economists — who will be treated further later — every
single hermeneutician, past and present, has been an avowed collectivist,
either of the left- or right-wing variety, and sometimes veering from one
collectivism to another in accordance with the realities of power. Marx, Veblen,
Schmoller, and the German Historical school are well known. As for the modern
hermeneuticians, Heidegger found it all too easy to become an enthusiastic Nazi
once the Nazi regime had been established. And Gadamer had no difficulty
whatever adapting either to the Nazi regime (where he was known for having only
a "loose sympathy" with the Third Reich) or to the Soviet occupation
in East Germany (where, in his own words, he won "the special esteem of
the Russian cultural authorities" for carrying out "their directives
exactly, even against my own convictions").[7]
"Openness" and Keeping the
"Conversation" Going
Here we must note two variants of the common
hermeneutical theme. On the one hand are the candid relativists and nihilists,
who assert, with an inconsistently absolutist fervor, that there is no truth.
These hold with the notorious dictum of the epistemological anarchist Paul
Feyerabend that "anything goes." Anything, be it astronomy or
astrology, is of equal validity or, rather, equal invalidity. The one possible
virtue of the "anything goes" doctrine is that at least everyone can
abandon the scientific or philosophic enterprise and go fishing or get drunk. This
virtue, however, is rejected by the mainstream hermeneuticians, because it
would put an end to their beloved and interminable "conversation."
In short, the mainstream hermeneuticians do not like
the "anything goes" dictum because, instead of being epistemological anarchists,
they are epistemological pests. They insist that even though it is impossible
to arrive at objective truth or indeed even to understand other theorists or
scientists, that we all still have a deep moral obligation to engage in an
endless dialogue or, as they call it, "conversation" to try to arrive
at some sort of fleeting quasi-truth. To the hermeneutician, truth is the
shifting sands of subjective relativism, based on an ephemeral
"consensus" of the subjective minds engaging in the endless conversation.
But the worst thing is that the hermeneuticians assert that there is no
objective way, whether by empirical observation or logical reasoning, to
provide any criteria for such a consensus.
Since there are no rational criteria for agreement,
any consensus is necessarily arbitrary, based on God-knows-what personal whim,
charisma of one or more of the conversationalists, or perhaps sheer power and
intimidation. Since there is no criterion, the consensus is subject to instant
and rapid change, depending on the arbitrary mindset of the participants or, of
course, a change in the people constituting the eternal conversation.
A new group of hermeneutical economists, eager to find
some criteria for consensus, have latched onto a Gestalt-like phrase of the
late economist Fritz Machlup, perhaps taking his name very much in vain. They
call this criterion the "Aha! principle," meaning that the truth of a
proposition is based on the exclamation of "Aha!" that the
proposition may arouse in someone's breast. As Don Lavoie and Jack High put it:
"We know a good explanation when we see one, and when it induces us to say
aha."[8] Somehow I do not find this criterion for truth,
or even for consensus, very convincing. For example, many of us would find the
prospect of being confronted with the option of engaging in endless and
necessarily fruitless conversation with people unable to write a clear sentence
or express a clear thought to be the moral equivalent of Sartre's No Exit.
Furthermore, I have a hunch that if someone came up
with the proposition: "It would be a great thing to give these guys a dose
of objective reality over the head" or at the very least to slam the door
on their conversation, that this would elicit many more fervent
"Ahas!" than the murky propositions of the hermeneuticians
themselves.
The prime moral duty proclaimed by the hermeneuticians
is that we must at all times keep theconversation going.
Since this duty is implicit, it is never openly defended, and so we fail to be
instructed why it is our moral obligation to sustain a process that yields such
puny and ephemeral results. In keeping with this alleged virtue, the
hermeneuticians are fervently and dogmatically opposed to "dogmatism"
and they proclaim the supreme importance of remaining endlessly
"open" to everyone in the dialogue. Gadamer has proclaimed that the
highest principle of hermeneutic philosophy is "holding oneself open in a
conversation," which means always recognizing "in advance, the
possible correctness, even the superiority of the conversation partner's
position." But, as Barnes points out, it is one thing to be modestly
skeptical of one's own position; it is quite another to refuse to dismiss any other position as false or mischievous. Barnes
points out that the modest skeptic:
recognizes that he himself may always be wrong. Gadamer's "open" philosopher allows that his opponent may always be right. A modest skeptic may … indeed, in his modest way, regard the history of philosophy as a ceaseless campaign, marked by frequent defeats and occasional triumphs, against the ever powerful forces of fallacy and falsehood.… [W]ith some opponents he will not be "open": he will be quite sure that they are wrong.[9]
The most important hermeneutical philosopher in the
United States is Richard Rorty, who, in his celebrated book, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, devotes
considerable space to the prime importance of "keeping the conversation
going." In his sparkling critique of Rorty, Henry Veatch points out that,
to the crucial question of how can we conversationalists ever know which ideals
or "cultural posits" (in the Rortian language) are better than
others, "Rorty could only answer that, of course, there can't be any such
thing as knowledge in regard to matters such as
these." So, if there is no knowledge and, hence, no objective criteria for
arriving at positions, we must conclude, in the words of Veatch, that
"although Aristotle may well have taught that 'philosophy begins in
wonder,' … present-day philosophy can only end in a total conceptual or
intellectual permissiveness."[10] In short, we end with the Feyerabendian
"anything goes" or, to use the admiring phrase of Arthur Danto in his
summary of Nietzsche, that "everything is possible."[11] Or, in a word, total "openness."
But if all things are open, and there are no criteria
to guide conversationalists to any conclusions, how will such conclusions be
made? It seems to me, following Veatch, that these decisions will be made by
those with the superior Will-to-Power. And so it is not a coincidence that
leading hermeneuticians have found themselves flexible and "open" in
response to the stern demands of state power. After all, if Stalin, Hitler, or
Pol Pot enters the "conversational" circle, they cannot be rejected
out of hand, for they too may offer a superior way to consensus. If nothing is
wrong and all things are open, what else can we expect? And who knows, even
these rulers may decide, in a sardonic burst of Marcusean "repressive
tolerance," to keep some sort of Orwellian "conversation" going
in the midst of a universal gulag.
In all the blather about openness, I am reminded of a
lecture delivered by Professor Marjorie Hope Nicholson at Columbia University
in 1942. In a critique of the concept of the open mind, she warned: "Don't
let your mind be so open that everything going into it falls through."
There is another self-serving aspect to the
hermeneutical demands for universal openness. For if nothing — no position, no
doctrine — can be dismissed outright as false or mischievous or as blithering
nonsense, then they too, our hermeneuticians, must be spared such rude
dismissal. Keeping the conversation going at all costs means that these people
must eternally be included. And that is perhaps the unkindest cut of all.
If one reads the hermeneuticians, furthermore, it
becomes all too clear that typically no one sentence follows from any other
sentence. In other words, not only is the style abominable, but there is no
reasoning in support of the conclusions. Since logic or reasoning are not considered
valid by the hermeneuticians, this procedure is not surprising. Instead, for
reasoning the hermeneuticians substitute dozens or scores of books, which are
cited, very broadly, in virtually every paragraph. To support their statements,
the hermeneuticians will list repeatedly every book that might possibly or
remotely relate to the topic. In short, their only argument is from authority,
an ancient philosophic fallacy which they seem to have triumphantly revived.
For indeed, if there is no truth of reality, if for logic or experience, we
must substitute a fleeting consensus of the subjective whims, feelings, or
power plays of the various conversationalists, then what else is there but to
muster as many conversationalists as possible as your supposed authorities?[12]
Armed with their special method, the hermeneuticians
are therefore able to dismiss all attacks upon themselves, no matter how
perceptive or penetrating, as "unscholarly." This lofty rebuttal
stems from their unique definition of scholarly, which for them means ponderous
and obscurantist verbiage surrounded by a thicket of broad citations to largely
irrelevant books and articles.
So why then have not the distinguished critics of
hermeneutics played the game on their opponents' own turf and waded through the
mountains and oceans of hogwash, patiently to cite and refute the
hermeneuticians point by point and journal article by journal article? To ask
that question is virtually to answer it.
In fact, we have asked some of the critics this
question, and they immediately responded in a heartfelt manner that they do not
propose to dedicate the rest of their lives to wading through this miasma of
balderdash. Moreover, to do so, to play by the hermeneuticians' own rules,
would be to grant them too much honor. It would wrongfully imply that they are
indeed worthy participants in our conversation. What they deserve instead is
scorn and dismissal. Unfortunately, they do not often receive such treatment in
a world in which all too many intellectuals seem to have lost their built-in
ability to detect pretentious claptrap.[13]
Hermeneutical Economics
"The hermeneuticians are able to dismiss all attacks upon themselves, no matter how perceptive or penetrating, as 'unscholarly.'"
Economists like to think of their discipline as the
"hardest" of the social sciences, and so it is no surprise that
hermeneutics — though having conquered the field of literature and made severe
inroads into philosophy, political thought, and history — has yet made very
little dent in economics. But the economics discipline has been in a state of
methodological confusion for over a decade, and in this crisis situation
minority methodologies, now including hermeneutics, have begun to offer their
wares in the economics profession; of course, the practitioners down in the
trenches only loosely reflect, or indeed have scarcely any interest in, the
small number of methodological reflections in the upper stories of the ivory
tower.
But these seemingly remote philosophical musings do
have an important long-run influence on the guiding theories and directions of
the discipline. For approximately two decades, Lionel Robbins's justly famous The Nature and Significance of Economic Science was
the guiding methodological work of the profession, presenting a watered-down
version of the praxeological method of Ludwig von Mises. Robbins had studied at
Mises's famous privatseminar at Vienna, and
his first edition (1932) stressed economics as a deductive discipline based on
the logical implications of the universal facts of human action (for example,
that human beings try to achieve goals by using necessarily scarce means). In
Robbins's more widely known second edition (1935), the Misesian influence was
watered down a bit further, coupled with intimations no bigger than a man's
hand of the neo-classical formalism that would hit the profession about the time
of World War II.[14] After the war, the older economics was inundated
by an emerging formalistic and mathematical neoclassical synthesis, of
Walrasian equations covering microeconomics and Keynesian geometry taking care
of macro.
Aiding and abetting the conquest of economics by the
new neo-classical synthesis was the celebrated article by Milton Friedman in
1953, "The Methodology of Positive Economics," which quickly swept
the board, sending Robbins's Nature and Significance unceremoniously
into the dustbin of history.[15]For three decades, secure and unchallenged, the
Friedman article remained virtually the only written portrayal of official
methodology for modern economics.
It should be noted that, as in the triumph of the
Keynesian revolution and many other conquests by various schools of economics,
the Friedman article did not win the hearts and minds of economists in the
pattern of what we might call the Whig theory of the history of science: by
patient refutation of competing or prevailing doctrines. As in the case of the
Mises-Hayek business-cycle theory dominant before Keynes's General Theory, the Robbins book was not refuted;
it was simply passed over and forgotten. Here the Thomas Kuhn theory of
successive paradigms is accurate on the sociology or process of economic
thought, deplorable as it might be as a prescription for the development of a
science. Too often in philosophy or the social sciences, schools of thought
have succeeded each other as whim or fashion, much as one style of ladies'
hemlines has succeeded another. Of course, in economics as in other sciences of
human action, more sinister forces, such as politics and the drive for power,
often deliberately skew the whims of fashion in their own behalf.
What Milton Friedman did was to import into economics
the doctrine that had dominated philosophy for over a decade, namely logical
positivism. Ironically, Friedman imported logical positivism at just about the
time when its iron control over the philosophical profession in the United
States had already passed its peak. For three decades, we have had to endure
the smug insistence on the vital importance of empirical testing of deductions
from hypotheses as a justification for the prevalence of econometric models and
forecasting, as well as a universal excuse for theory being grounded on
admittedly false and wildly unrealistic hypotheses. For neoclassical economic
theory clearly rests on absurdly unrealistic assumptions, such as perfect knowledge,
the continuing existence of a general equilibrium with no profits, no losses,
and no uncertainty, and human action being encompassed by the use of calculus
that assumes infinitesimally tiny changes in our perceptions and choices.
In short, this formidable apparatus of neoclassical
mathematical economic theory and econometric models, all rests, from the
Misesian point of view, upon the treacherous quicksand of false and even absurd
assumptions. This Austrian charge of falsity and unreality, if noticed at all,
was for decades loftily rebutted by pointing to Friedman's article and
asserting that falsity of assumptions and premises do not matter, so long as
the theory "predicts" properly. In its founding years in the early
1930s, the Econometric Society emblazoned on its escutcheon the motto,
"Science is prediction," and this was the essence of the Friedman-derived
defense of neoclassical theory. Austrians such as Mises and Hayek replied that
the disciplines of human action are not like the physical sciences. In human
affairs, there are no laboratories where variables can be controlled and
theories tested, while (unlike the physical sciences) there are no quantitative
constants in a world where there is consciousness, freedom of will, and freedom
to adopt values and goals and then to change them. These Austrian contentions
were dismissed by neoclassicals as simply posing a greater degree of difficulty
in arriving at the human sciences, but not in offering a troublesome difference
in kind.
The neoclassical synthesis, however, began, in the
early 1970s, to lose its power either to understand or to predict what was
going on in the economy. The inflationary recession that first appeared
dramatically in the 1973 — 74 contraction put an end to a 35-year period of
arrogant and unquestioned hegemony by the Keynesian wing of the neoclassical
synthesis. For Keynesian theory and policy rested on the crucial assumption
that inflationary recession simply cannot happen. At that point, Friedmanite
monetarism came to the fore, but monetarism has now come a cropper after making
a rapid series of disastrously wrong predictions from the beginning of the
Reagan era until the present. But he who lives by prediction is destined to die
by prediction.
In addition to these failures of Keynesianism and
monetarism, the blunders and errors of econometric forecasting have become too
notorious to ignore, and a wealthy and supremely arrogant profession, using
ever higher-speed computer models, seems to enjoy less and less ability to
forecast even the immediate future. Even governments, despite the assiduous
attention and aid of top neoclassical economists and forecasters, seem to have
great difficulties in forecasting their own spending, much less their own
incomes, let alone the incomes or spending of anyone else.
Amid these failures, there has been a chipping away at
the neoclassical formalism of Walrasian microeconomics, sometimes by
disillusioned leaders operating from within this ruling paradigm.
As a result of these problems and failures, the last
10 or 15 years has seen the development of a classic Kuhnian "crisis
situation" in the field of economics. As the positivist neoclassical
orthodoxy begins to crumble, competing paradigms have emerged. Sparked also by
Hayek's receipt of a Nobel Prize in 1974, Austrian or Misesian economics has
enjoyed a revival since then, with numerous Austrians teaching in colleges in
the United States and Britain. Recently there have even emerged five or six
Austrian graduate programs or centers in the United States.
In a crisis situation, of course, the bad jostles the
good in the new atmosphere of epistemological and substantive diversity. No one
ever guaranteed that if a hundred flowers should bloom, that they would all be
passing fair. On the left, the nontheory of institutionalism has made a bit of
a comeback, jostled by "post-Keynesians" (inspired by Joan Robinson)
and "humanistic" neo-Marxists who have substituted a vague adherence
to "decentralization" and protection of all animal and vegetable life
forms for the rigors of the labor theory of value. Which brings us back to
hermeneutics.
For in this sort of atmosphere, even the underworld of
hermeneutics will vie for its day in the sun. Probably the most prominent
hermeneutical economist in the United States is Donald McCloskey, who calls his
viewpoint "rhetoric" and whose attack on truth occurs in the name of
rhetoric and of the eternal hermeneutical conversation.[16] McCloskey, unfortunately, follows the modern
path of rhetoric run hog-wild and divorced from a firm anchor in truth,
overlooking the Aristotelian tradition of "noble rhetoric" as the
most efficient way of persuading people of correct and true propositions. For
Aristotelians, it is only "base" rhetoric that is divorced from true
principles.[17]McCloskey is now organizing a center for rhetorical
studies at the University of Iowa, which will organize volumes on rhetoric in a
number of diverse disciplines.
Much as I deplore hermeneutics, I have a certain
amount of sympathy for McCloskey, an economic historian who endured years as a
drill instructor and cadre leader in the Friedman-Stigler Chicago school's
positivist ranks. McCloskey is reacting against decades of arrogant positivist
hegemony, of an alleged "testing" of economic theory that never
really takes place, and of lofty statements by positivists that "I do not
understand what you mean," when
they know darn well what you mean but disagree with it, and who use their
narrow criteria of meaning to dismiss your argument. In this way, the
positivists for a long while were able to read virtually all important
philosophical questions out of court and consign them to the despised
departments of religion and belles letters. In a sense, the rise of
hermeneutics is those departments' revenge, retorting to the positivists that
if "science" is only the quantitative and the "testable,"
then we shall swamp you with stuff that is really meaningless.
It is more difficult to excuse the path traveled by
the major group of hermeneuticians in economics, a cluster of renegade
Austrians and ex-Misesians gathered in the Center for Market Processes at
George Mason University. The spiritual head of this groupuscule, Don Lavoie,
has reached the pinnacle of having his photograph printed in his magazine Market Processtalking to the great Gadamer.[18] Lavoie has organized a Society for Interpretive
Economics (interpretation is a code word for hermeneutics) to spread the new
gospel, and has had the effrontery to deliver a paper entitled "Mises and
Gadamer on Theory and History," which, as a colleague of mine has
suggested, is the moral equivalent of my writing a paper entitled "Lavoie
and Hitler on the Nature of Freedom."
It must be noted that nihilism had seeped into current
Austrian thought before Lavoie and his colleagues at the Center for Market
Processes embraced it with such enthusiasm. It began when Ludwig M. Lachmann,
who had been a disciple of Hayek in England in the 1930s and who had written a
competent Austrian work entitled Capital and Its Structure in
the 1950s, was suddenly converted by the methodology of the English economist
George Shackle during the 1960s.[19] Since the mid-1970s, Lachmann, teaching part of
every year at New York University, has engaged in a crusade to bring the
blessings of randomness and abandonment of theory to Austrian economics. When
Lavoie and his colleagues discovered Heidegger and Gadamer, Lachmann embraced
the new creed at the 1986 first annual (and, if luck is with us, the last
annual) conference of the Society of Interpretive Economics at George Mason
University. The genuine Misesian creed, however, still flourishes at the Ludwig
von Mises Institute at Auburn University and in its publications: The Free Market, the Austrian Economics Newsletter, and
the Review of Austrian Economics, which in its first
issue included a critique of a quasi-hermeneutical book by two ex-Misesians who
claim to have discovered the key to economics in the works of Henri Bergson.[20]
One of the main motivations of the ex-Misesian
hermeneuticians is that their horror of mathematics, to which they react as to
the head of Medusa, leads them to embrace virtually any ally in their struggle
against positivism and neoclassical formalism. And so they find that, lo and
behold, institutionalists, Marxists, and hermeneuticians have very little use
for mathematics either. But before they totally embrace the desperate creed
that the enemy of my enemy is necessarily my friend, our Market Process
hermeneuticians should be warned that there may be worse things in this world
than mathematics or even positivism. And second, that in addition to Nazism or
Marxism, one of these things may be hermeneutics.
And just as Professor McCloskey's history may serve as
a partial mitigation of his embrace of hermeneutics, we may go further back and
mitigate the sins of the logical positivists. For, after all, the positivists,
much as they may be reluctant to admit it, also did not descend upon us from
Mount Olympus. They grew up in old Vienna, and they found themselves in a
Germanic world dominated by protohermeneutical creeds such as Hegelianism as
well as by the young Heidegger, who was even then making his mark. After
reading and listening to dialectics and protohermeneutics day in and day out,
after being immersed for years in the gibberish that they were told constituted
philosophy, is it any wonder that they — including for our purposes Popper as
well as Carnap, Reichenbach, Schlick, et al. — should finally lash out and
exclaim that the whole thing was meaningless or that they should cry out for
precision and clarity in language? Is it also any wonder that the nascent
positivists, like McCloskey a half-century later, should go too far and throw
out the philosophic baby with the neo-Hegelian bathwater?
Notes
[1] Barnes, "A Kind of Integrity"; and
David Gordon, "Hermeneutics versus Austrian Economics" (Auburn, Ala.:
Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1986).
[2] Eric Voegelin, "The German University and
the Order of German Society: A Reconsideration of the Nazi Era,"Intercollegiate Review 20 (Spring/Summer 1985):
11.
[4] Karl R. Popper, The Open Society and its Enemies, 4th ed. (New York: Harper
& Row, 1962), 2, p. 33.
[6] H.L. Mencken, "Professor Veblen," A Mencken Chrestomathy (New York: Alfred A. Knopf,
1949), p. 270.
[8] Don Lavoie and Jack High, "Interpretation
and the Costs of Formalism" (unpublished manuscript), p. 14.
[9] Barnes, "A Kind of Integrity," p. 13.
For a critique of the triumph of the ideal of "openness," see Allan
Bloom,The Closing of the American Mind (New York: Simon
and Schuster, 1987).
[10] Henry Veatch, "Deconstruction in
Philosophy: Has Rorty Made It the Dennouement of Contemporary Analytical
Philosophy?" Review of Metaphysics 39
(December 1985): 313 — 14, 316.
[11] Arthur C. Danto, Nietzsche
as Philosopher (New York: Columbia University Press, 1980), p.
12; cited in Veatch, "Deconstruction," p. 312.
[12] I am indebted for this point to Sheldon Richman
of the Institute for Humane Studies at George Mason University.
[13] In a witty and perceptive article, the
distinguished Yale philosopher Harry Frankfurt calls this phenomenon
"bullshit," which he asserts to be a greater enemy to the truth than
an outright lie, since a liar recognizes that he is violating the truth whereas
the bullshitter does not. Frankfurt writes:
The contemporary
proliferation of bullshit also has deeper sources, in various forms of
skepticism which deny that we can have any reliable access to an objective
reality and which therefore reject the possibility of knowing how things truly
are. These "antirealist" doctrines undermine confidence in the value
of disinterested efforts to determine what is true and what is false, and even
in the intelligibility of the notion of objective inquiry.
See Harry Frankfurt, "On Bullshit," Raritan 6 (Fall 1986): 99 — 100.
[14] Milton Friedman, "The Methodology of
Positive Economics," in Friedman, Essays in Positive Economics (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1953).
[15] Lionel Robbins, An Essay
on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science (London:
Macmillan, [1932] 1935).
[16] Donald N. McCloskey, The Rhetoric of Economics (Madison: University of
Wisconsin Press, 1985). For a comprehensive Misesian critique of McCloskey's
work, see the book review essay by Hans-Hermann Hoppe, "In Defense of Extreme
Rationalism: Thoughts on Donald McCloskey's The Rhetoric of
Economics," Review of Austrian Economics 3 (1989): 179 —
214.
[17] Cf. Richard M. Weaver, The Ethics of Rhetoric (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press) and Larry Arnhart,Aristotle on Political
Reasoning: A Commentary on "The Rhetoric" (DeKalb:
Northern Illinois University Press, 1981).
[19] Ludwig M. Lachmann, Capital and Its Structure (London: London School
of Economics, 1956). The later, post-Shackelian or nihilist Lachmann may be
found in his "From Mises to Shackle: An Essay on Austrian Economics and
the Kaleidic Society," Journal of Economic Literature 54
(1976).
[20] Thus, see Charles W. Baird, "The Economics of Time and Ignorance: A
Review," Review of Austrian Economics1
(1987): 189 — 223.
No comments:
Post a Comment