High stakes for law
enforcement
In the
aftermath of the terrorist bombing—no lesser word will do—at the Boston
Marathon, a major debate has broken out over the proper law enforcement
procedures in two key areas: general surveillance and targeted searches. Many
insist that a general right to privacy should limit the first, and that concern
with racial and ethnic profiling should limit the second. Both of these
overinflated concerns should be stoutly resisted.
The
task of unearthing terrorist activities is like looking for a needle in the
haystack. Even the best system of oversight and surveillance will turn up an
extraordinarily high percentage of false positives, for the simple reason that
the odds of any given lead providing useful information, although hard to
estimate, may be very small. It takes, therefore, a very large payoff indeed to
justify government action in those cases, which is why police surveillance and
monitoring should receive high priority only in cases where the risk justifies
the large public expenditures and the serious intrusions on privacy of those
targeted individuals. At this point, the questions arise of what kind of
surveillance should be used, and when and how law enforcement officials can
target particular individuals.
The Way Forward on Surveillance
The
Tsarnaev brothers’ attack at the Boston Marathon has brought forth an insistent
public call for an increase in surveillance to detect suspicious activities
before it is too late. To be sure, there are always technical difficulties in using surveillance devices. But
any objection on that ground should be treated solely as means-ends questions,
which can in large measure be answered by improved software in such key areas
as facial recognition detection. The moral, social, and constitutional
objections are sadly misplaced.
Yet,
post bombing, intense political opposition has arisen in Massachusetts over the
wider use of drones and other surveillance devices at next year’s Boston
Maraton. Republican Sen. Robert Hedlund of the Massachusetts Legislature has
sponsored restrictive legislation on drones with two key provisions. First, the
legislation would prohibit the generalized use of drones in Boston, without the
explicit prior approval of local governments, including the Boston City
Council. Second, the legislation would “prohibit data collection about lawful
peaceful activity,” which in turn would be backed up by public disclosure of
drone use.
Hedland’s
stated rationale runs as follows:
It’s not surprising that you have law enforcement agencies rushing out to use [the Boston bombing and subsequent manhunt] as pretext to secure additional powers but I think we have to maintain perspective and realize that civil liberties and the protections we’re granted under the Constitution and our rights to privacy, to a degree, are nonnegotiable. . .
You don’t want to let a couple of young punks beat us and allow our
civil liberties to be completely eroded. I don’t fall into the trap that,
because of the hysteria, we need to kiss our civil liberties away.
Hedlund
is dead wrong here—and this is from a writer whose entire career has been
devoted to imposing workable and principled limitations on government power.
First,
the essential task of government is to preserve the life, liberty, and property
of all individuals within its jurisdiction against their forcible destruction
by other individuals. Second, a system of ex post (after the fact) criminal
punishments forms at best only one part of a coherent and comprehensive
strategy.
Compensation
after the fact from terrorists is rarely, if ever, available. And even if it
should magically materialize, it does not bring dead people back to life or
heal the wounded. Criminal sanctions will not deter suicide bombers, nor can
they be meted out in proportion to the mayhem that these people cause. Major ex
ante (before the fact) precautions are imperative to stop the endless loss of
life and limb that ex post sanctions cannot deter.
Nor is
there any “pretext” at work in insisting on greater deterrence. It is easy to
pooh pooh a major social threat like terrorism by reducing it to the conduct of
“young punks,” the very people most likely to engage in violent activity.
Unfortunately,
Hedlund compounds his initial error with two further mistakes. His first is
constitutional, with the false claim that our rights of privacy under the
Constitution are “nonnegotiable.” Fortunately, no provision of the United
States Constitution requires this rigid and destructive point of view.
The
basic command of the Fourth Amendment says that, “The right of the people to be
secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable
searches and seizures, shall not be violated . . .” For these purposes, the
operative term is “unreasonable,” which, in light of the weighty interests on
all sides of the dispute, requires some public judgment that compares the risks
of inaction with those of excessive action. This unavoidable balancing process
makes it foolish to elevate privacy—itself a complex notion—to that
“nonnegotiable” status under a Constitution that also values the protection of
life, liberty, and property.
Second,
the last thing needed in these difficult circumstances is a squeamishness about
aggressive government action. It is wholly unwise to think that we can turn
surveillance devices on and off with the flip of a switch, as Hedlund proposes,
and still get the information we need. The correct approach is to do exactly
what Hedlund would stop: collect troves of information about the conduct of
people in public places,
which can then be stored for future use.
The key
protection of civil liberties lies in the restricted access and use of that
information. Unauthorized use is subject to severe penalties and should be
invoked to allow for the full collection of the relevant information. Indeed,
similar activities have to take place in monitoring the Internet use of
suspected terrorists—and similar constraints must apply. The information can be
collected and reviewed for limited law enforcement purposes, so long as its
unauthorized release or use is subject to heavy criminal sanctions.
One
great advantage of this comprehensive approach to surveillance in public places
is that it avoids the risk that the surveillance will be conducted in a
discriminatory fashion. The collection of information covers everybody who
comes to public places. Yet once the information gathered reveals some
potential targets, it then justifies closer surveillance of key individuals who
can be singled out by their past activities. As the evidence gets stronger, so
too does the case for more aggressive law enforcement actions. Whenever
possible, these enhanced government activities should be subject to some kind
of independent oversight, similar to the surveillance warrants of the FISA courts, which deal with the wiretaps
that are in place today.
Reasonable Suspicion and the Terry Stop
The
need for expedited action also applies to individual decisions of law
enforcement personnel operating on suspicion, where the immediacy of the
situation makes it difficult, if not impossible, to introduce an added layer of
judicial protection.
As far
back as 1969, the United States Supreme Court, speaking through Chief Justice
Earl Warren in Terry v. Ohio, held, after much hand wringing, that a
police officer did not have to show probable cause in order to stop and frisk a
person on public streets. Reasonable suspicion that unlawful activity might
happen was all that was needed to justify what are now commonly called “Terry stops.”
Justice John Marshall Harlan tightened the noose still further by noting that
whenever the police had enough reason to stop a person, the right to frisking
him followed “automatically” given the ever-present risk that the party stopped
might be carrying a concealed weapon.
This
decision has generated many complaints about racial profiling, an issue that
the Warren Court was well aware of at the time. There is no reason to sugarcoat
the painful choice. These frisks are honest-to-goodness searches and they can
be highly intrusive, covering even intimate body parts where weapons could be
concealed. They are also more likely to be conducted in high-crime areas with a
disproportionate number of young African-American males. No one can deny the
unhappy fact that a huge number of erroneous searches will take place, for which
there is, after the fact, no effective remedy at all. Unsuccessful searches
yield no evidence that could be rendered inadmissible at trial.
Yet
there are no sensible alternatives to the Terry rule. It surely makes no sense
to stop and frisk a proportionate number of white males for no reason. In
addition, it is virtually impossible to construct an intelligent system of ex
post compensation to redress the large number of low-level harms that
undoubtedly occurred when an innocent person was frisked.
Terry was unusually candid in recognizing that
it chose the best of a bad lot, by allowing substantial errors in order to
protect against yet greater losses. The Terry court further hedged its bets by
announcing that its ruling applied only to this particular case. But history
has not worked out that way. Today reasonable suspicion virtually always
justifies the search and the frisk that follows.
Clearly,
the stakes on ethnic profiling are higher than ever after the Boston
Marathon—which makes it all the more important to keep the law in focus.
Jonathan Chait recently wrote a short piece in New York Magazine entitled:
“Profiles in Profiling: From the appalling New York Post to the rest of us.” He
observed:
The Muslim world has certainly produced more than its share of
terrorists. But there is a conceptual fallacy at the root of the nativist
paranoia the Post (and other elements of the Murdoch media) have eagerly
exploited: One cannot infer from the fact that many terrorists are Muslims the
conclusion that many Muslims are terrorists.
No one
should offer any defense of the irresponsible journalistic sensationalism that
Chait rightly attributes to the Post. But the defenders of increased
surveillance are not making the crude leap of logic with which they are
charged. Everyone knows that two propositions are all too true: First, the vast
majority of individuals with Muslim background are not terrorists, and, second,
a disproportionate number of terrorists are Muslim. It is that last fact that
drives the need for further surveillance, notwithstanding the high error rate
captured in the first observation.
Indeed,
it seems as though the FBI had received intelligence from Russian authorities
that Zubeidat Tsarnaeva, the mother of the Tsarnaev brothers, was
herself a potential terrorist. With that, any doubts about Russian intelligence
or the motivations of the brothers falls by the wayside. Law enforcement
officials must follow such leads to their bitter end in dealing with the
prevention and deterrence of terrorist activities. The quicker public officials
shed their reluctance to move decisively in these areas, the safer we all shall
be.
No comments:
Post a Comment