The balance between liberty and security in criminal cases
Matters of criminal procedure were not much in evidence in the aftermath
of the bombings at the Boston Marathon. Nary a peep of protest was raised
against the massive lock-down and manhunt that followed hard on the heels of
that senseless tragedy.
But now that some degree of normalcy has returned, it is important to
think about these procedural issues. To that end, two recent Supreme Court
cases address law enforcement and the Fourth Amendment. Florida v. Jardines
deals with searches in connection with illegal drug trafficking and Missouri v.
NcNeely addresses compelled blood tests on suspected drunk drivers.
Both of these cases return to fundamental questions that have previously
divided the Court. What is remarkable about the Supreme Court’s recent Fourth
Amendment jurisprudence is that these divisions are not apparent. The opinions
in both cases lack reference to the endless theoretical debates between the
hard-nosed originalists and the equally insistent defenders of the “Living Constitution.”
In consequence, these close decisions have generated strange alliances that
have transcended the deep five-to-four conservative-liberal split.
Back to Constitutional Basics
To
understand why, it is useful to start with the complete text of the Fourth
Amendment.
The right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers,
and effects, against unreasonable searches and seizures, shall not be violated,
and no Warrants shall issue, but upon probable cause, supported by Oath or
affirmation, and particularly describing the place to be searched, and the
persons or things to be seized.
The
impulse for the Amendment was the 1765 English case of Entick v. Carrington, where Lord Camden refused to allow
public officials to ransack the plaintiff’s premises under “general warrants.”
His decision inspired the Warrant Clause of the Fourth Amendment, which required
government officials to “particularly describe” what they hoped to search or
seize.
Today,
as a theoretical matter, all nine Supreme Court justices rightly recognize
that Entick supplies
the indispensable first step for dealing with an age-old problem—namely, the
extent to which the police may infringe on the ordinary rights of individuals
to personal liberty and private property in order to control criminal activity.
No justice thinks that the police should have unlimited discretion in this
area. Yet none doubts that the police perform vital functions needed for the
preservation of our ordered liberty.
Since
all the justices are working to balance the same set of considerations, modern
decisions in this area tend to focus on setting the right balance in hard
cases. On this point, the key insight is one that all nine justices undervalue,
the need for bright-line rules in routine cases.
Drug Busts and Privacy
In Jardines, the Supreme Court
had to decide whether the government conducted a search when it brought a
trained drug-sniffing dog on a six-foot leash to the front door of the
Jardines’ house, where it went wild after sniffing the cannabis that was
growing inside. It is remarkable that a fact pattern this simple could provoke
a five-to-four split, where Justice Antonin Scalia, joined by Justices Thomas,
Ginsburg, Sotomayor, and Kagan, found an unconstitutional search. That decision
was met by a dissent from Justice Alito, joined by Justices Roberts, Kennedy,
and Breyer.
Scalia’s
position was that bringing a dog onto the property near the house—into the
so-called curtilage—was done with the specific purpose of finding out what went
on inside the walls of the house. In my view, his ultimate position was clearly
correct. That outcome rests on a simple analysis of what a search is: a
purposive act made in order to discover new information. Therefore, an
accidental discovery, such as when a police officer just happens to smell odors
coming from the street while engaged in other business, is not a search. The
means by which this (deliberate) search takes place bears no relationship to
the resolution of the constitutional issue.
Unfortunately,
Justice Scalia embellished that basic insight with two unneeded qualifications.
First, he insisted that under our Fourth Amendment jurisprudence, the “home is
first among equals.” Textually, however, “houses”—which are less intimate than
“homes” anyhow—receive no priority over persons, papers, and effects. Indeed,
it is easy to imagine cases where the violation of these other three interests
could give rise to equal or greater umbrage. As a matter of sound textual
interpretation, it is always risky to introduce fine distinctions among items
that are bracketed together in the original text.
Next,
Justice Scalia held that the case was simple because the police invaded the
Jardines’ curtilage in order to conduct their search. But the offensive search
here was not about what was found in that location, but the information behind
closed doors. Property is thus a means to protect privacy, a broader notion.
Yet that information might in some cases be discoverable by a skilled dog or
other instrumentality that the police operated from Jardines’ front gate, the
public streets, or a neighbor’s porch. In these instances, the quantum of
relevant information is the same as that found from the trespass itself.
So the
question arises of why the protection of the home diminishes because the
deliberate search takes place from a somewhat more remote location. The
well-known 1967 Supreme Court decision in Katz v. United States had already made it clear, in some
cases at least, that a trespass into some protected space was not necessary to
create a Fourth Amendment violation. In that case, the government agents
attached an electronic listening device to the outside of a public phone booth
to gather evidence about the illegal gambling activities of the accused. The
phone booth was said to be a place where anyone enjoys a reasonable expectation
of privacy.
There
is a similar expectation in Jardines,
even though there was no “physical” invasion of the premises. The police entry
is not subject to constitutional oversight because the sniffing dog trampled a
blade of grass. Rather, the protection of the privacy interest dominates. No
private individual could escape a damage action for invasion of privacy if he
or she listened to intimate conversations from a distance. The government
should fare no better in this context.
In
dealing with this case, Justice Scalia had to address the government’s
contention that its entrance onto the property did not constitute a trespass
because of the standing common law rule that gives ordinary people an “implied
license” to enter the property. In his dissent, Justice Alito pushed this
notion by noting that people are normally allowed to beat a path to the front
door for a wide range of social and business purposes, and need only retreat
once they are told to leave.
Justice
Scalia, however, is far more faithful to the common law rules when he
concludes, “The background social norms that invite a visitor to the front door
do not invite him there to conduct a search.” This little debate vividly shows
how good constitutional law depends critically on mastering common law
principles, which Justice Alito failed to do.
The
common law recognizes two classes of permitted entrants—business invitees and
social guests. These may differ in the degree of protection that they receive
against physical injury on the premises, but those refinements are irrelevant
here because all permitted entrants propose transactions that work for the
benefit of the landowner. In contrast, the landowner gives no consent, express
or implied, to those who enter with hostile intent, like the government
officials here. The simple rule gets this case right, and offers greater
clarity to law enforcement personnel and property owners alike, without any
needless qualifications.
The Forfeited Rights of Drunk Drivers
In McNeely, a deeply divided
Court revisited the question of whether the police must obtain a search warrant
before drawing blood from an errant driver who refused to submit to a breath
test that measured his alcohol concentration. The traditional view, articulated
by the late Justice William Brennan in the 1966 case of Schmerber v. California, put forth two propositions that are in
tension with each other.
The
first was that drawing blood from a person counts as both a search and a
seizure of the person, which it surely does. The second was that owing to the
“exigent circumstances” stemming from the rapid decay of blood alcohol, the
arresting officer could order that search without first getting a warrant or
showing the more exacting “probable cause” requirement that the Constitution
imposes for many searches.
In my
view, Justice Brennan (who was very solid on Fourth Amendment issues) got the
issue right when he adopted aper
se (or across-the-board) rule approving these searches. The
level of intrusion is both low and uniform, and the gains from the controlling
of drunk driving are sufficiently large, that this per se rule is a
sensible safe harbor in an area that condemns all “unreasonable searches and
seizures.”
Unfortunately,
in McNeely, Justice
Sotomayor took a wrong turn by concluding that the prohibition against
unreasonable searches and seizures requires arresting police officers to
conduct a detailed factual examination to determine whether the rate of decay
of blood alcohol justifies ordering the blood test without the benefit of a
warrant.
But
just what is to be gained by this “fact-intensive” analysis conducted on a
case-by-case basis? For starters, the admitted violation of traffic rules gives
clear evidence that something is amiss. In and of itself, it surely provides
reasonable suspicion for thinking alcohol may be involved, and perhaps even the
probable cause needed to execute the warrant.
Everyone
knows that blood alcohol decays at a rapid rate, even if that rate is not
uniform across all persons. Just running this time-consuming evaluation could
result in critical delays in obtaining fast-disappearing evidence, which could
make any test inconclusive. Besides, it is highly unlikely that any remote
magistrate would be willing to deny the request for a warrant here, so that the
case-by-case approach leads to both higher error and administrative costs.
There
is a sobering lesson here. Bright-line rules may not work in every case, but in
this particular instance, there has not been the slightest peep of general
protest with the uniform application of the Schmerber rule since it was first
announced close to 50 years ago. But Sotomayer’s new case-by-case rule may not
play out so well. It is a delusion to think that individualized decisions
always lead to better outcomes.
One
clear anxiety is whether the police discretion could mask racial-profiling,
which is, without question, a highly divisive and emotional issue today. The ad
hoc outcomes under McNeely invite
such charges, because the discretion that is said to protect privacy can also
be used to single out certain groups for unwelcome scrutiny. Jardines, on the other
hand, will not generate any such backlash to the extent that it
controls police behavior.
Taking
both cases together sends a clear message. Some issues of course will involve
matters of degree. No one has a magic formula to determine what counts as
reasonable suspicion or probable cause. But that knowledge should not stop the
search for clean and workable rules. With Jardines, that approach gives somewhat greater
protection to potential criminals; with McNeely,
it gives somewhat less. But the public wins both times. The ability to craft
sensible per se rules
leads to better results overall, which, when all is said and done, leads to the
right balance of liberty and security that everyone desires in Fourth Amendment
cases.
No comments:
Post a Comment