A dangerous temptation
by Kenneth Minogue
Societies are all imperfect, but self-interested societies fare far better than any of their counterparts.
by Kenneth Minogue
Societies are all imperfect, but self-interested societies fare far better than any of their counterparts.
Here in
the Galapagos, the abstraction that must haunt our imaginings is evolution. But
the term has two distinct meanings. Here is one genealogy, from Hayek:
Modern biology has borrowed the concept of evolution from studies of culture of older lineage. If this is in a sense well known, it is almost always forgotten.
Of course
the theory of cultural evolution [sometimes also described as psycho-social,
super-organic, or exsomatic evolution] and the theory of biological evolution
are hardly identical.
Here is
another, from Matt Ridley:
Thomas Hobbes was Charles Darwin’s direct intellectual ancestor. Hobbes (1651) begat David Hume (1739), who begat Adam Smith (1776), who begat Thomas Robert Malthus (1798), who begat Charles Darwin (1859).
Evolution
is clearly a powerful word. The problem is that neither of these meanings has
much to do with Darwinian natural selection which, by contrast with these
meanings, is a blind process in which random mutations constantly generate new
versions of a species that deals more successfully with the environment than
its fellows. My concern by contrast is with the emergence of our free
civilization, which has no blind random processes in it, though it may well be
that Adam Smith’s “invisible hand” might be taken to function in the same way.
I am
concerned with the evolution of that grand thing called a “free
society”—specifically, the only society or civilization that has ever evolved
into freedom: our own.
What I
mean by this is that our society—namely modern Western Europe and its offshoots
in the rest of the world—has evolved into a set of national states, each of
which is an association of individualists, managing their own lives and
pursuing their own individual projects. That might sound like a description of
any kind of human life, so why am I suggesting that it is unique?
The
contrast I want to make here is with every other society and civilization
because all of them rest, at some level, on legitimation in terms of a
comprehensive system of justice. Most such societies are of course largely
agricultural, and in them each individual notionally occupies a social status
valued according to its supposed contribution to the common good. Human beings
living in these just societies live—in principle—the way all human beings ought
to live: in castes, or under Sharia, or the Mandate of Heaven, or whatever the hierarchy
of belief locally may be, down to and including small tribal groups.
We in
Western Europe, however, have taken a different path in which individualists,
often identified as town-dwellers or “bourgeoisie,” associate together
generally according to their own inclinations rather than in terms of some
determinate social status designed to contribute to the good of the community.
Individualists (in their very role as individualists) merely associate rather
than form a community, though as subjects of a state they may participate in
various communities built around specific interests or passions—clubs,
religions, industrial enterprises, and so on. But this is incidental to the
free lives they lead.
Those
who live in just societies have clear functions, and up to a point enjoy the
respect appropriate to such a function. Some of these functions are precisely
defined: ruler, wife, warrior, priest, etc. But in all cases there will be a
well-understood hierarchy governing social life, and its purpose is to preserve
the basic aspiration of such comprehensively just societies—namely, social
harmony. Thus the Forbidden City in Beijing had a Gate of Supreme Harmony
leading to the Hall of Supreme Harmony, passing on to the Hall of Central
Harmony and the Hall of Preserving Harmony, all of them clearly issuing from
the idea of individual imperial authority.
Individualists
in free societies, by contrast, merely have a duty to conform to the laws of
their state, which ideally do not distinguish specific functions. In advancing
this distinction, I am obviously perilously engaged in an abstract sociological
sketch, one at a level comparable to David Riesman’s famous distinction between
people living in traditional and modern societies in The Lonely Crowd.
In these terms, free individualists are notionally equal under the law,
including the ruler himself or herself. But what is it, we may ask, that guides
and motivates the lives of these free individualists? The common answer is:
self-interest. And my central concern in this paper will be with making sense
of this remarkable—and troublesome—term.
In an
obvious sense, we all know what “self-interest” means. If a car comes careering
towards me, I jump out of the way; it is the basic instinct of
self-preservation, and hardly distinguishes an individualist from any other
human being. More specifically, as self-interested, I prefer to get a higher
rather than a lower wage for the same work. Again, I want my family to prosper
and my children to do well at school. Obvious, in fact.
It
should be clear that the meaning of self-interest must be understood as
responding to the situation of individuals moving from a traditional to a
modern society. In a traditional society, politics (to the extent that such a
thing may be recognized amid absolutist justice) is not about interests but
about ideals, and most notably about justice itself. People may be nice or
nasty, selfish or generous, but the sphere of their actions is largely
determined by the role or status they have. But as we move into an urbanized
modern society, increasing numbers of individuals must find some niche or
enterprise of their own within which to live. They must become, as it were,
self-reliant so as not, if possible, to become a burden on others, and in order
to respond to their own responsibilities. This virtue of self-reliance, more
exactly than the idea of self-interest, recognizes the situation of the
individualist as modernity spreads and people move from the countryside to the
towns.
In
spite of its necessary place in responding to modernity, there is a great deal
of hostility towards the idea of self-interest. It is associated with ruthless
self-promotion, taking no account of the good of others. It is sometimes
thought to be at war with common decency, and even a form of exploitative
attitudes to others. We sometimes think that La Rochefoucauld got it right in
remarking, “We all have courage enough to bear the troubles of others,” in
addition to his many other cynical remarks. Or we may take our bearings from
Gore Vidal: “It’s not enough to succeed. Others must fail.” Or even the
fictional Gordon Gecko: “Greed is good.” And at that point, self-interest has
become quite explicitly identified with the vice of selfishness.
It is
common ground, of course, that human beings are fallible and sinful creatures,
much given to what Hobbes recognized as vainglory. Hobbes was particularly
impressed by the pleasure humans take in thinking they are superior to
others—being “foremost” as Hobbes put it. Hobbes thought he was talking of all
men, and his account of human nature was certainly always true of prominent men
and women, but it is plausible to think that Hobbes was particularly
generalizing the individualists of his own time. Christianity of course
emphasizes the place of foolish vanities in human lives. But there is nothing
essentially individualistic about such human imperfections. They are universal.
All human beings exhibit such weaknesses.
It is
also noticeable, however, that free individualists are remarkably generous and public
spirited, and not only because they belong to richer societies. They are
generous in helping the poor all over the world, in responding to remote
catastrophes, and in endowing museums and other cultural institutions.
Individualists can also exhibit the most remarkable solidarity in helping each
other in difficult situations. In spite of their supposedly isolating and
selfish individualism, their capacity for spontaneous fruitful cooperation if a
crisis occurs is striking. They have succeeded in creating societies in which
the vulnerable are helped, and in which women may live on equal terms with men
in ways hardly to be imagined in some “superior” just societies. The test of
these judgments lies not in any “Eurocentric” vanity, but in the fact that millions
from supposedly just and perfect societies will do almost anything to migrate
into our vile, self-interested, capitalist world.
In
spite of these facts, two remarkable beliefs have come to be widely held about
free, Western societies.
The
first is that human beings are naturally selfish creatures, and that they can
only become virtuous by overcoming their natural self-partiality. This moral
opinion descends from some versions of Christianity, was powerfully taken up by
French moralists in the seventeenth century, contributed to satirical views of
commerce in the early eighteenth century, was influentially refuted by Adam
Smith, and was revived to plague us once more by the Marxists (and other
ideologists) in the nineteenth century. But the individualist, in pursuing
self-interest, is not, according to our critics, overcoming self-partiality.
The
second and related view is that Western Civilization is technically prodigious
but has basically failed to overcome prejudice, superstition (e.g. religion),
bigotry, racism, imperialism, national selfishness, and other such evils from
which only the wisdom of international organizations can save us. This curious
form of civilizational self-hatred results not from judging that we are worse
than others but from the belief that since we have more control over our
nature, we ought to have been able to do better.
We
have, then, a problem and a solution. The problem is how to give a more or less
neutral account of the broad motive that animates our free societies, and the
common solution is to say that it is “self-interest.” But then we discover that
the expression “self-interest” loses its neutrality, and thus cannot function
without becoming pejorative. We might, I have suggested, replace self-interest
with self-reliance, but that would be to identify free societies with a virtue.
What to do? We must, I think, look again at the character of the free societies
we inhabit.
How did
our free society emerge, evolve, develop . . . get off the ground? The answer
is that it has emerged from an immensely complex set of social and moral
contingencies, and even to ask about its “causes” is hopelessly to simplify the
remarkable thing that has emerged. Some signs of it may be found in the peoples
to whom we look back with admiration—the Greeks and Romans, most notably, but
also the Jews and, later, the various barbarian peoples who moved into the
western Empire. The form that Greek philosophy took, and its flourishing from
Thales to Aristotle and beyond, clearly became one of the central resources of
our freedom. The Romans valued this feature of classical Greek culture, and
passed it on to those working to turn the Christian revelation into a faith
that could animate new ways of life. But there were many other elements of
social life that adumbrated the possibility of free relations between
individuals—for example the consultative practices of feudal monarchies that
came to be generalized in England by Magna Carta. And the common account of our
civilizational past, the story that takes us from the Greeks to the present
over a period of several millennia, amounts to a sketch of how this new thing
emerged.
The
obvious move would be to consider the “causes” of this new thing, but “cause”
is too crude an idea for this task. Instead, we must imagine a vast range of
face-to-face encounters between Europeans, over a long period under many varied
circumstances, changes of demeanor which sometimes evolved into doctrines or
explicit practices—such as chivalry—but which were more commonly slight variations
in manners and moral assumptions, feeding slowly into institutional practices
(in universities as they emerged, for example) that, towards the end of what we
call “the Middle Ages” began to make it clear that something quite new was
coming into existence. For institutional change emerges spontaneously from
personal responses.
The
growth of modern natural science is one example of how a tradition—in this
case, of philosophical questioning—became the route into a quite new
intellectual adventure as it came to involve enterprising thinkers in countries
ranging from Poland to France and Britain. But perhaps the most notable verbal
sign of something new happening was the rising currency, from the seventeenth
century onwards, of words hyphenated with “self-”—as in my central example of
“self-interest.” In this idiom, human experience was being bifurcated into two
elements—a subjective and an objective part—and it was registered in language
by the recognition of “self,” often as a kind of managing agent in how human
beings respond to the world.
My
concern is with “self-interest,” but there is an endless sequence of such
hyphenated terms emerging from the seventeenth century onward. Such terms might
be used by individuals explaining themselves, or they might be used
analytically, or critically, by outsiders. “Self-expression” might be a good
thing, but being “self-opinionated” was generally not. In moral discourse, the
distinction between “self” and “others” came to be prominent, and approval was
likely to focus on how any particular “self” responded to “others.” In
traditional societies, a focus on “others” obviously had been possible, but in
that context the “others” were more commonly specified in terms of their
relative social status. They were less likely to be merely abstract “others.”
Thinking in these terms led many to the cynical view that underneath most,
indeed perhaps all, social life would be found a destructive selfishness. A
common thought was that the men of this period were living through a period of
decline.
The
real significance of the “self-interest” formula is that it reveals to us some
elements of the basic conflict in our society between freedom on the one hand
and justice on the other. Here is an expression that might merely mean a rational
response to circumstances, or could signify the moral fault of selfishness (and
it was often assumed to do just that), but there can be little doubt that its
usage has generally been pejorative. It thus constitutes the basic premise that
slides to, rather than actually entails, the idea that a free society is
essentially unjust because the strong, in pursuing their interests, oppress the
vulnerable, and hence that justice requires that the state should take steps to
restore, by political action, the fairness that has been lost in the very
operation of the economic process. The “strong” in these cases might turn out
to be the rich, or the enterprising, or those who have better “social capital”
because of more fortunate family life, or such further variations of the idea
of “privilege” as may respond to the discovery of relative (rather than merely
absolute) deprivation. On such a view, a free market economy is essentially
unfair because the basic drive animating it has no moral content.
Individualists in pursuit of self-interest are merely seeking benefits for
themselves. And yet, in the real world, morally valuable and cooperative
behavior is evidently a feature of our modern societies. The question thus
becomes: How might we describe such virtue in our real world, and how account
for it?
The
answer, of course, has generally been in terms of the virtue of altruism or
benevolence, which, as distinct from self-interest, is recognized as the model
of goodness when it occurs between “self” and “others.” It is this contrast
that is at the heart of a good deal of moral theorizing. Our world is full of
benevolent people performing prodigies in order to raise money for charities.
This is one way of showing that they are not spending their lives merely
pursuing their own interests. Such activities are clearly admirable. But as
exhibitions of virtuous conduct, they raise problems.
The
first problem is that the virtue of benevolence can attach itself, like a
parasite, merely to the having of good intentions. The crimes of communist
regimes often avoided censure by virtue of the supposed good intentions of
those committing them. Again, people lacking integrity (in, for example,
exploiting claims for expenses) commonly defend themselves by the claim that
they had broken no rules. Further, the term “interest,” even in the moral
context of “self-interest,” invokes politics, understood as an arena in which
interests conflict with each other. Hence at its least sophisticated, one form
of self-ascribed good intentions may be the mere fact of supporting welfarist
political policies. Such a view, not uncommon in leftish parties, takes the
illusion of costless good intentions to its limit.
And
this leads us to a second defect of this version of the moral life: That
altruism and benevolence, as the essence of goodness, cast into the shade such
more elusive and subtle virtues as integrity and courage. One notable collapse
of integrity consists in the happy belief that the costs of one’s policies will
be borne by others, and particularly in politics, by the more heavily taxed
rich. Just such a belief is a popular recourse in the more demagogic versions
of current politics. Such a view corresponds precisely to the corruption that
Greek philosophers diagnosed in democracy as a political system, understanding
it as an instrument by which the poor might plunder the rich.
Even
the device of off-loading the costs of one’s public altruism on the taxable
rich, however, is merely a political solution to the problem, and what politics
gives, politics can also take away. The ideal solution to such a problem is—an
ideal! The public altruism of welfare must be entrenched in the ideals of
justice and of rights. A real solution to the conflict between self and others
must transcend this distinction itself, for in a real community, cooperation
transcends conflicts of interest between individuals. Such, I think, is the
logic behind our admiration for “social justice,” however difficult we may find
it to define. And it seems to me that in the concept of justice, in its
contrast with self-interest, we have one clue to the destiny of our free
society: That we shall never quite be free of the illusion that our
psychological foundation in self-interest is the imperfection, the vice, that
stands in the way of the social and human perfections that would create a
better world.
And it
is in terms of this move to social justice that we leave our free societies
behind and find ourselves entertaining a comprehensive system of justice
understood as the right and fair and just outcome of economic enterprise. Our
Western understanding of merely civil justice in a free society cannot lead to
any precise conception of a right order of things (as entertained in other
civilizations), because no free process can be relied upon to guarantee any
particular outcome. It is further important that no particular outcome, if it
did occur, could then be protected against later change. Freedom is thus
incompatible with any version of comprehensive justice.
The
point is that justice in our Western understanding is thought to be (in
principle) a freely accepted rule that mitigates some problem arising from a
pre-political condition, often theorized as a “state of nature.” This
understanding of civil law in no way depends on whether we take the story of
the state of nature seriously. What is fundamentally involved is a recognition
that justice in a free society comes from the needs of the ruled, and that it
consists in a process of rules that could not generate any particular desired
outcome. Historically generated rules of law based upon this basically
contractual order of social relationships were early professionalized in Europe
and embedded in our governing practices as a limitation upon the caprice of
executive action.
What we
may call “the moral life” as it exists among Western Europeans emerges directly
from these conditions. Practical moral judgments result from asking, in a moral
sense, “what ought I to do in this situation?” and in most societies, the
appropriate answer is given by religion, or by custom, or by the realities of
situational power.
Both
religion and custom will also be found in European states, of course, but the
moral life as we experience it may be distinguished from these concerns. It
consists in judgments balancing reasons about the consequences of alternative
actions for the interests of both the actor and those his act will affect. It
is, in principle, no less independent of custom and religion than the Socratic
model of living the right kind of life which our moral practices (very
distantly) echo. Custom and religion may become influences, but only as
elements in a process of moral calculation. That is one element of what is
individualistic about such a moral practice, and it may affect both actions
that come within the ambit either of the distinction between good and evil or
of right and wrong. An important element in the moral life as Max Weber
analyzed it resulted from the Protestant judgment that a holy life could be
lived in the world, rather than requiring immersion in a specialized religious
institution. And as the modern world developed, the aristocratic concern with
honor became generalized into various criteria of identity such as conscience
and reputation. In other words, the competitive character of every other
feature of free modern societies became a feature more in our moral life than
in the economy. The outcome has been that in this area, as in most others,
Europeans found themselves living within a world of conflicting understandings
about what ought to be done. And it was precisely in embracing this and other
forms of conflict that Europeans recognized themselves as free.
Some
people take the view that we in the West are fortunate to enjoy freedom,
because it is a universal human aspiration that has been commonly frustrated in
most societies. This is one of the more pernicious illusions we entertain about
human kind. Most people have never lived in free societies, nor exhibited any
desire or capacity for freedom. Totalitarian movements reveal even the danger
that many who have enjoyed freedom can be happy to abandon it in the name of
some passionate cause. The illusion that everyone wants to be free means only,
perhaps, that people don’t much like being frustrated, but that is quite
different from the self-discipline involved in an association of individualists
managing their own lives. This illusion has been happily indulged by many
commentators on the “Arab Spring” of recent times, in which the instability of
authoritarian regimes might suggest a whiff of libertarian feeling. What most
people seem to want, however, is to know exactly where they stand and to be
secure in their understanding of their situation.
Rules
and processes are risky because they will produce unexpected and sometimes
unwelcome outcomes, and it is this contrast which makes freedom constantly
vulnerable to those who try to seduce us with dreams of perfection. My argument
has been that even perfectly valid ways of explaining ourselves can easily
slide into pejorative accounts of freedom. When that happens, it can seem
obvious that governments should not merely regulate the economy (as they must
as part of the rule of law in modern societies) but that they should also
intervene to manage its outcomes by the use of subsidy redistribution and welfarism.
These policies are suggested by the slide from a descriptive account of human
psychology (the pursuit of self-interest) to a corrupt identification of the
description with the vice of selfishness, ruthlessness, greed, and similar
evils. The reality of pursuing self-interest in a free modern society is no
doubt better described by invoking some such virtue as self-reliance, but that
is the demand which a free society makes on everyone, and it is that demand
which is often found burdensome by those who find security in a structure of
welfare from which they may benefit.
Much of
this corruption may be regarded as political sentimentalism. I am not, of
course, suggesting that individuals do not suffer in many ways from the ups and
downs of economies and the many other conditions that invoke the concept of
vulnerability. But politics can, of course, only respond to abstract classes of
suffering—such as that of unemployed people, or drug addicts, or pregnant
teenagers. The real situation of individuals in these classes is immensely
variable. In political discussion it can only be grasped in terms of some image
or archetype. Democratic politics extensively consists of the conversion of
abstract classes of vulnerability or hardship into images of a persuasive kind.
And politically, there is no doubt which way expenditure on these imaged
policies will go. It rises relentlessly upwards. The classes of the vulnerable
multiply, and the demands on the public purse rise in order to deal with
problems that in earlier generations were accommodated within the exigencies of
family life.
In
politics, every policy has some advantages and also some disadvantages. But
notable about the disadvantages of this range of welfarist reforms is that they
have led most rich Western states into a condition of chronic bankruptcy. The
crisis of the early twenty-first century is no doubt attributable to bankers
and to other public actors, but unmistakably central to the problem is a level
of both personal and public debt, which is unsustainable, and will get worse
for more than demographic reasons. And when governments become indebted, they
have virtually no solutions to the problem except to deceive their populations
with inflation and other monetary forms of smoke and mirrors.
It is
not merely governments that act corruptly. It is also the democratic voter. As
we have seen, the demos is also corrupted. A great deal of political
sentimentalism floats on the illusion that rising public expenditure would not
affect most of the population because the rich can be taxed more heavily. Much
indignation is often expended about large firms that “avoid” taxation, as if
taxation were a form of charity one should offer to governments, rather than
known rates to be paid by specific and well-defined classes of taxpayer. The
problem is in part that the rules of taxation have become so complicated that
skilled professionals are needed to reveal what must be paid and what may be
kept. Politicians however are keen to talk of the rich “paying their share” of taxation;
it is a cry advanced under the popular rubric of “fairness.” It is only as it
dawns upon voters that the costs of welfare cannot forever be loaded onto the
rich without serious economic consequences that public opinion turns against
welfare spending.
My
argument is, then, that societies are necessarily imperfect, and making them
perfect is not an option for creatures such as humans. We can, however—up to a
point—choose where imperfection may least harmfully find an outlet in our
complicated societies. And in making this judgment, we need to remember the
practice of freedom on which our wealth seems to have depended. Solutions that
reduce our freedom put modernity itself at risk.
The
experience of twentieth-century politics presents us with an obvious
alternative. We can accept the inequalities of economic life as necessary
imperfections, or we may try to correct them by taking decisive political
action, which means greatly expanding the power of states so that they may use
their power to make economic outcomes more just. It will hardly be news that
expanding the power of states has seldom been anything but a risky option. In
the twentieth century, states taking over the economy generated
totalitarianism. Merely to refer to the body count of those bold experiments is
enough to rule that option out of contention. Here today, we are well into the
twenty-first century, with a history of increasing welfarist policies long
established, and they have led us to unsustainable levels of debt.
The
unavoidable conclusion seems to me to be that letting economies rip, however
much we may disapprove of the consequences, is much the better option. For one
thing, it leaves open the possibility that the more vigorous members of society
will take some action themselves to mitigate, at least in part, the sufferings
of those genuinely in need of help. The balance in our tradition between the
rules we must respect because they are backed by the authority of law, and the
free choice in the other elements of our life is one that free agents rightly
will not wish to see disturbed.
It
seems to me that our preoccupation with the defects of our civilization is a
standing temptation, and a dangerous one, to have recourse to civil authority
in order to deal with what we may be persuaded to understand as social
imperfections. And that preoccupation with our imperfections is most commonly
grounded in the corrupt sense of explaining freedom in terms of self-interest.
To recap, such an assumption about the motivation of moderns invokes the moral
criterion of justice or fairness as condemning many of the consequences of our
economic life (in terms of the supposed distribution of benefits). Such a view
in turn generates a succession of vulnerable classes of people each with claims
on the state for redress. Welfare programs responding to this process have no
determinate end in sight. There is no viable conception of a society without
vulnerable classes demanding special treatment as victims of one or other kind
of injustice or unfairness. We begin to conceive of modern societies as
associations of incompetents and cripples, which is absurd. The human condition
is not like that. We entertain many foolish ideas, and no doubt will continue
to do so. But this is a piece of nonsense that we can no longer afford.
No comments:
Post a Comment