Let’s bash the idea that some kids aren’t genetically
cut out for learning
By FRANK FUREDI
One of the dirty secrets of the modern British
educational establishment is that it lacks faith in the ability of education to
make a significant difference to people’s lives. This is the most interesting
thing about the publication of a document attributed to Dominic Cummings, who
until recently served as a special adviser to the Tory secretary of state for
education Michael Gove: it lets this secret out; it openly acknowledges the low
expectations that policymakers have of children and of schools.
Cummings is unequivocal on this point. He believes
that what mainly determines pupils’ performance is not the quality of teaching,
but their IQ levels and genetic inheritance. He claims that up to 70 per cent
of a child’s performance levels are genetically derived. That’s another way of
saying that teachers and schools can have at best a marginal impact on
children, whose fate is apparently bestowed on them by their genes.
Many critics have tried to depict Cummings as a
right-wing ideologue using genetic determinism to push elitist ideas. What they
mostly object to is not his claim that nature trumps nurture, but the fact that
he also dismisses today’s English education as mediocre. However, the
differences between Cummings and his critics are not as deep as they might
first appear. While there might be a fundamental difference in their
assessments of the state of English education, both sides share a pessimistic
view of the power, or rather lack of power, of education.
Cummings’ genetic determinism offers an insight into
how cultural and social differences are naturalised these days, hardened into
inalterable facts of life. In Cummings’ worldview, differences among children
that are actually changeable and fluid are turned into given, immutable facts.
But genetic determinism is only one of many forms of determinism that dominate
the intellectually impoverished landscape of pedagogy in the twenty-first
century. In recent years, policymakers looking for quick-fix technical
solutions to educational problems have enthusiastically embraced the promise of
neuroscience and behavioural psychology. Science can provide important insights
into the workings of the children’s cognition, of course; but scientific
advocates go way too far when they insist that neuroscience – not teaching –
will revolutionise the classroom. They, too, embrace a socio-biological outlook
that one-sidedly looks at the differences in children’s classroom achievements
as something determined by nature.
One of the most depressing things about the current
discussion on schooling is the education establishment’s lack of belief in the
power of ideas. Instead of encouraging teachers to gain mastery of their
subjects, so that they might inspire their students with the quality of their
thinking, pedagogues prefer to put their faith in the latest gimmick or
motivational techniques to try to manage classroom behaviour. So-called reforms
and ‘pedagogic innovations’ now completely bypass the question of how best to
cultivate the intellectual growth of the young. Instead, they draw upon market
and psychological research to devise schemes that promise to motivate students.
Educationalists
believe this new psycho-pedagogy – whether focused on learning styles, brain
functioning, thinking skills, emotional intelligence or multiple intelligence –
will help them to engage with students. Such pedagogy is obsessed with learning styles and
is devoid of any interest in the content of the knowledge
being taught. Policymakers have very little interest in the intellectual
content of education; in fact, all too often their new policies implicitly, and
sometimes explicitly, advocate the devaluation of the role of knowledge
acquisition and intellectual development within educational institutions.
Saving children
from elitist education
In the
twenty-first century, low expectations about children’s intellectual
capabilities come in many forms. Some claim young children are not school-ready
because of their mothers’ and fathers’ alleged lack of ‘parenting skills’.
Others blame the distractions of the media for children’s inability to think
and learn. Many educators believe that children from disadvantaged backgrounds
can only respond to education that relates directly to their experience, and
therefore there is little point in teaching them more abstract academic
subjects.
The implicit
assumption is always that a significant section of working class-children
cannot cope with exposure to a rigorous academic curriculum; so the way forward
is to downsize education in order to make it relevant to those with limited
intellectual abilities. Like Cummings, these educationalists and observers also
have a low regard for the capacity of schools to make much of a difference to
the lives of pupils.
Some educators
believe that developing a less academic and more skills-focused form of
education represents a progressive blow against older, elitist forms of
schooling that are based on a knowledge-led curriculum.
These days, many
professional educators condemn academic curriculums as ‘irrelevant’, as elitist
nineteenth-century relics. Yet considering that intellectual and scientific
development occurred, and continues to occur, through distinct academic
subjects, it is far from evident why a curriculum based on literature,
mathematics, history, biology and physics should be outdated. The knowledge
that children gain through studying these subjects is no more outdated today
than it was 100 or 200 years ago. The charge that an academic curriculum is
outdated is rarely informed by any serious reflection on the content of
subjects. Rather, such anti-academic criticisms are a product of the
sensibility of low expectations in relation to the power of schooling. From
this perspective, a subject-based curriculum is looked upon as being far too
difficult for most children.
For Dominic
Cummings, what a teacher can achieve in the classroom is fundamentally limited
by pupils’ genetics and IQ. Paradoxically, many of his critics who dismiss his
socio-biological approach actually agree that little can be done in the
classroom to cultivate the intellectual and academic growth of children. They
also think that many children’s lack of social or cultural capital prevents
them from dealing with a serious, intellectually informed common curriculum.
This point was forcefully argued by Professor John White, one of the leading
critics of having a subject-based curriculum. He says subject-led education
discriminates against children from poor homes because they are likely to
struggle in a ‘highly academic school culture’.
White is probably
right when he says poorer children are likely to face difficulties when they
engage with a ‘highly academic school culture’. Indeed, most children –
including those from the middle classes – are likely to be stretched by an
academic school culture. But the role of educators is to establish an
environment in which children are helped to overcome the obstacles standing in
the way of their attaining a good academic education. Decrying the value of
such an education avoids confronting the real challenge: how to provide such a
high-quality education to everyone, regardless of their social circumstances.
It also
significantly underestimates the human capacity for learning. Sadly, today’s
fashionable pedagogy of limits distracts society’s attentions from the fact
that education has a formidable potential to help people more fully realise
their humanity and their powers.
The weight
attached to the significance of individual differences between children
obscures what is common about their development. There is a
body of educational theory which argues, in the words of one author, that ‘in
general terms, the process of learning among human beings is similar across the
human species as a whole’. Indeed, no system of education can work effectively
unless it is based on general principles that can speak to the needs of a
cohort of children. An effective pedagogy must involve starting ‘from what
children have in common as members of the human species’, says one study, in
order to ‘establish general principles of teaching and, in the light of these,
to determine what modifications of practice are necessary to meet specific
individual needs’.
Yet as late as the
1940s, official reports argued that there were three types of children – ‘those
that are good with abstract ideas, those that are good with their hands, and
those who are simply good’. The UK education system was organised in such a way
that children with ‘innate’ academic qualities were segregated from those who
needed to be trained for a manual occupation. This hierarchy of educational
opportunities reflecting people’s different social circumstances was justified
on the basis that some children were cut out for specific roles in society. One
argument used was that since children had different innate capacities, as
measured by IQ, academic learning was only suitable for a small minority. In
the twenty-first century, the dominant etiquette of social inclusion means
old-fashioned talk about a hierarchy of abilities is out of favour – which is
why the education establishment is likely to be critical of Cummings’ explicit
endorsement of any such hierarchy.
However, many
educators who are hostile to traditional ideas about a hierarchy based on
ability have little reservation about adopting other, usually psychologically
informed ways of differentiating pupils. Through the use of psychological
research and diagnostic instruments, a new ‘psycho-pedagogy’ has emerged that
labels and categorises children according to the ‘learning styles’ or
‘intelligences’ they allegedly possess.
Indeed,
psycho-pedagogy has invented a veritable dictionary of labels that can be used
to diagnose children’s ‘learning styles’, ‘aptitudes’ and ‘intelligences’. Some
pupils have visual skills, while others have auditory skills, and others still
apparently have kinaesthetic learning styles. Learners are categorised as
innovators, adaptors, reflective, pragmatic, etc. Policymakers have invented
the terms ‘gifted’ and ‘talented’ to categorise able students. Such terms are
meant to convey a sense of scientific precision. So gifted students are the top
five to 10 per cent of pupils ‘as measured by actual or potential achievement
in the main curriculum subjects’, says the British government’s Excellence in
Cities programme. Today’s curriculum engineers have turned stereotyping into an
artform. They helpfully provide a glossary of terms that can be used to
describe ‘gifted’ and ‘talented’ children. The glossary includes terms like
‘able pupils’, ‘more able pupils’, ‘the very able’, ‘exceptionally able’,
‘gifted children’, ‘talented pupils’, ‘those with exceptional talent’, ‘pupils
with marked aptitude’.
The belief that
many children are not likely to be motivated by an intellectually based
curriculum is given legitimacy by theories claiming that there are different
types of children with different profiles of intelligence. In previous times,
those who were pessimistic about child development argued that children’s
futures were determined by their innate intelligence levels. In the first half
of the twentieth century, the claim that children’s intelligence was
genetically inherited and fixed served as an explanation for differential rates
of achievement. From this perspective it could be argued that a significant
percentage of children would not benefit from an academic education. In more
recent times, this pessimistic view of children’s potential has been
discredited, which is why Cummings seems out of touch – but unfortunately, some
of the current theories of child development also convey an element of fatalism
about the potential of children to benefit from an academic education
Many of Cummings’
critics are exercising double standards when they accuse him of elitism. They are
no less elitist in their approach, since they also assume that a significant
number of children are unlikely to thrive in a rigorous intellectual climate.
Both sides of this discussion subscribe to a form of determinism that assigns
an undistinguished role to the school.
Yet schools really
matter. They particularly matter for children from a disadvantaged background.
Schools can provide such children with the kind of knowledge that can, to a
degree, compensate for their relative lack of access to cultural capital in
their home lives. All children, regardless of their social background and
ability, can benefit from a good education. What they achieve is not
pre-determined by genes any more than it is by their social background.
Fatalistic pedagogy in all its different guises is a copout. A humanist and
future-oriented pedagogy should take as its starting point what all children
have in common – a capacity to learn and to develop through a shared cultural
interaction and shared experiences.
Many practitioners
of the pedagogy of difference are well-meaning individuals, believing that
their differentiated approach represents a sensitive response to the reality of
children’s lives. But fatalistic pedagogy undermines the very purpose of
education. Whether it points the finger at children’s genes or their learning
styles, fatalistic pedagogy refuses to assume full responsibility for the
education of young people. It is modern educationalists’ attitude of low
expectations that ensures that so much of schooling is about going through the
motions rather than really educating. If English education is really mediocre,
as Cummings contends, is it not because we now have an educational
establishment that doesn’t believe in education?
No comments:
Post a Comment